24/7 writing help on your phone

To install StudyMoose App tap and then “Add to Home Screen”

The Impact of Vices on Student Motivation and Academic Performance

Save to my list

Remove from my list

The Pervasiveness of Vices Among Students

Alcoholism: a persistent challenge.

Prof. Finch

The Smoking Dilemma

The allure of computer games, gambling: a growing trend, exploring the impact on student motivation and academic performance.

The Impact of Vices on Student Motivation and Academic Performance. (2016, Apr 02). Retrieved from https://studymoose.com/vices-intoduction-essay

"The Impact of Vices on Student Motivation and Academic Performance." StudyMoose , 2 Apr 2016, https://studymoose.com/vices-intoduction-essay

StudyMoose. (2016). The Impact of Vices on Student Motivation and Academic Performance . [Online]. Available at: https://studymoose.com/vices-intoduction-essay [Accessed: 24 Jun. 2024]

"The Impact of Vices on Student Motivation and Academic Performance." StudyMoose, Apr 02, 2016. Accessed June 24, 2024. https://studymoose.com/vices-intoduction-essay

"The Impact of Vices on Student Motivation and Academic Performance," StudyMoose , 02-Apr-2016. [Online]. Available: https://studymoose.com/vices-intoduction-essay. [Accessed: 24-Jun-2024]

StudyMoose. (2016). The Impact of Vices on Student Motivation and Academic Performance . [Online]. Available at: https://studymoose.com/vices-intoduction-essay [Accessed: 24-Jun-2024]

  • Academic achievement or academic performance is the extent to which a student Pages: 8 (2340 words)
  • The Crucible: An Exploration of Human Vices. Pages: 5 (1455 words)
  • Impact of Internet Usage on Academic Performance of the Student Pages: 4 (973 words)
  • Students’ Financial Responsibility, Academic Motivation, and Academic Success Pages: 5 (1269 words)
  • The Role of Grades in Student Motivation and Academic Success Pages: 3 (819 words)
  • School Uniform Requirements: Effects On Student Academic Performance Pages: 2 (360 words)
  • EFFECTS OF TIME MANAGEMENT ON THE ACADEMIC PERFORMANCE OF STUDENT ATHLETES OF UNIVERSITY OF SAINT LOUIS TUGUEGARAO Pages: 4 (930 words)
  • Pros and Cons of Mixed Schools: Impact on Academic and Social Performance Pages: 4 (1147 words)
  • Stress in Student Athletes: Mental, Physical, and Academic Impact Pages: 7 (1917 words)
  • The Impact of Online Gaming Towards the Academic Performance Pages: 2 (517 words)

The Impact of Vices on Student Motivation and Academic Performance essay

👋 Hi! I’m your smart assistant Amy!

Don’t know where to start? Type your requirements and I’ll connect you to an academic expert within 3 minutes.

Virtues and Their Vices

Placeholder book cover

Kevin Timpe and Craig A. Boyd (eds.),  Virtues and Their Vices , Oxford University Press, 2014, 528pp., $120.00 (hbk), ISBN 9780199645541.

Reviewed by Bradford Cokelet, University of Miami

Kevin Timpe and Craig A. Boyd offer us twenty-two chapters that discuss a host of specific virtues and vices (sections 1-4) and reflect on the role of virtue in various disciplines (section 5). The papers on the specific virtues and vices are organized into four traditional categories -- cardinal virtues, capital vices and corrective virtues, intellectual virtues, and theological virtues -- and these seventeen articles make up the heart of the collection. As this categorical scheme might suggest, most of the authors discuss and defend Christian accounts of the virtues and vices, and the collection effectively draws one (theist or not) into thinking about how Aquinas-inspired virtue theory can speak to people today.

Before getting into the details, I should say that several articles could be fruitfully used in a contemporary moral problems or introduction to philosophy class, and that the articles in sections 1-3, perhaps coupled with some of the recent work on Kant's account of virtue, could deeply enrich discussion in an upper-level or graduate course on virtue theory or virtue ethics. These chapters allow non-theistic philosophers to glimpse the concrete ways in which theistically understood virtues promise to aptly structure and orient the psychologies, practices, and activities of people and communities who are oriented by a religious conception of the good. By extension, they provide a useful framework to ask questions about the specific virtues that those with very different conceptions of the good will need to embody or reflectively cultivate in order to embody their ideals or values.

I cannot discuss all twenty-two articles or even summarize critical reactions to the core group of seventeen. Instead, I am going to highlight some of the aspects of the collection as a whole that will make it especially valuable for teachers and scholars. I am going to leave aside the last five chapters, which explore interesting questions about virtue in different disciplines but which are not tightly integrated with the larger whole. These chapters are, however, well done. Philosophers interested in virtue in theology, civic virtue in political liberalism, virtue in positive psychology, neuroscience and virtue, and virtue and a feminist ethics of care are encouraged to take a look at them. Helpful overviews of these papers can be found in the editors' introduction (29-32).

Turning to what I think is the core of the collection, I want to begin by re-iterating that many of these papers will be of interest to philosophy teachers, theist and non-theist alike. Representative options here include the chapters "Lust and Chastity", "Gluttony and Abstinence" and "Sloth". They introduce various historical conceptions of the virtues, compare their relative strengths and weaknesses, and invite readers to either adopt a revised historical conception or think about what alternative virtue and vice concepts they can develop in their place. For example, Rebecca Konyndyk DeYoung's entry on sloth explains that on one traditional understanding of sloth, restless multi-taskers, and not just slackers, count as slothful. On this view, sloth involves a failure to mindfully and zealously embody devotion to the good in one's activities, and it therefore need not be associated with a lack of worldly ambition or be contrasted with the view that work is more important than leisure or family. This historical discussion helpfully reminds us that our ordinary assumptions about specific virtues and vices may be the result of historical contingencies, but it also pushes us to think about how our psychologies must be shaped if we are to be zealously and energetically oriented toward the good (however we conceive of it).

Colleen McCluskey's chapter on lust and chastity and Robert B. Kruschwitz's on gluttony and abstinence have arguments that get a bit more contentious, but this just adds to their appeal. McCluskey nicely discusses what Aquinas might say in response to Simon Blackburn's argument that lust can be a virtue and, while rejecting Blackburn's approach, she argues for an Aquinas-inspired position that is revised to fit contemporary thinking or common sense. Like DeYong's essay on sloth this one illustrates that the virtues enable us to embody love for (or appreciation of) the good in our activities and relationships and that they therefore enable us to live well. But McCluskey sounds another theme that runs through the collection: that to live intelligently or prudently we need to be oriented towards the right kinds of goods and be oriented towards them in a structured way that reflects their comparative value.

In the discussion of lust and charity, for example, we are invited to reflect on the goods of sexual pleasure in and out of various kinds of relationship, to reflect on our conceptions of better and worse relationships, and to then think about how we would need to be psychologically constituted in order to be aptly oriented towards the good of sexual pleasure and its relation to other goods. In Kruschwitz's discussion of gluttony and abstinence, we are invited to reflect on analogous questions regarding the pleasures of eating and drinking. In each case we are also asked to think about how the pleasures we take in one kind of thing (e.g., food) can give energy and enjoyment to activities that embody or nurture even greater goods (e.g., family meals that nurture good family relations). Taken together, these chapters encourage us to think about how we can best temper and cultivate our desires for various creature comforts, so that they will become integrated with our more distinctively human desires to embody our ideals or values and live a good life. These chapters invite us to develop, in other words, a concrete conception of temperance, as that virtue is insightfully discussed by Robert C. Roberts in section one.

Most of the essays in sections one and two have something instructive to say about how the virtues enable us to be energetically and aptly oriented by a hierarchically structured and integrated conception of the good, but they also discuss how vices or shortcomings in virtue can lead to disordered, or just plain bad, lives. This theme comes to the fore, but does not dominate, in the chapters that discuss the vices of avarice, anger, envy, and pride. Taken together, these chapters remind us that our characteristically human concerns for long term safety, control, power, social standing, and self-esteem can distort our thinking about and relationships with others, as well our ability to pursue our own good. Given the religious framework of many of the authors it is unsurprising that they get us to think about how these vices can distort one's proper relationship with God. But they also make many insightful points about how our disordered or inapt emotions, deliberations, and volitions can corrupt our relations to friends, family members, communities, etc. and inhibit our ability to successfully and prudently pursue worthwhile life-projects. Moreover, these reflections are coupled with ones about the virtuous (well-ordered and apt) emotions, deliberations, and volitions and the way they contribute to good relationships and successful, excellent projects. These chapters are all interesting in their own right, but also link to varying degrees with the insightful earlier chapters on prudence, fortitude, and justice, and the later ones on the theological virtues of faith, hope, and charity.

As a non-theist, I found the later set of overlaps particularly interesting because they allowed me to start to see what theists might have in mind when they claim that the theistic virtues in some way infuse and improve the shared "pagan" ones that non-theists recognize. For example, in "Charity: How Friendship with God Unfolds in Love for Others" Paul J. Wadell invites the reader to think about how friendship with God could not only justify and motivate love for enemies and strangers, or buttress our hope when we are in dire straights, but how it could also, "deepen and perfect," our more central attachments to family, friends, and community (384-85). More specifically, he says that the relation to God calls on us to be "more attentive, focused, and faithful in love" to our near and dear (384).

To a non-theist such claims can remain opaque and apparently ungrounded, and this collection provides some real help in this regard. When trying to make sense of the view that the theological virtues transform or infuse the moral ones, you can revisit the earlier chapters on the specific virtues and vices that enable or inhibit our abilities to be attentive, focused, and faithful in love and to be energetic and devoted in our pursuit of worthwhile projects. You can look in these chapters for clues about how a loving relationship with God could be thought to deepen and perfect the moral virtues that are recognizable as virtues in a non-theistic framework. At least in my case, this provoked an initially plausible, if somewhat obvious, suggestion: that various ordinary vices and short-comings in virtue are grounded in our inflated, unduly negative, or fragile sense of self-worth or self-esteem, and that by entering into a loving relationship with God you can at least in principle (and perhaps with graceful intervention or co-operation) adopt a warranted and resilient sense of your worth. Now this is only one possibility. Non-theists might accept the claim about the common cause of vice and then offer an alternative story about how agents can develop a warranted and resilient sense of self worth -- drawing on the responses to this problem that we find in Kant, Aristotle, or the Buddhists, for example. But I hope this example illustrates the way that this collection allows one to think critically both about how to develop a theistic account of the virtues and their role in the good life, and the way that the account helps non-theists see how they can benefit by engaging with more traditional theistic conceptions.

My comments up to now have focused on the sections that discuss the moral and theological virtues, and I want to end with some brief comments about the section on the epistemic virtues. This section has three excellent essays by philosophers working in the virtue epistemology tradition -- Linda Zagzebski on trust, John Greco on knowledge and understanding, and Jason Baehr on theoretical wisdom/ sophia . Taken together these essays provide a lucid and inviting overview of the epistemic virtues and the ways that virtue epistemology enriches our thinking about epistemic assessments, strategies, and goals. Given the larger theme of the collection (virtues and their vices), however, I was left wanting a substantive discussion of various epistemic vices. For example, it would have been very nice to see what virtue epistemologists, especially theologically informed ones, can add to our thinking about epistemic injustice of the sort discussed by Miranda Fricker or to hear more about the epistemic issues that come up in thinking about moral education. More generally, the collection naturally provokes questions about how epistemic, moral, and theological virtues and vices might be inter-twined, and it would have been nice to have some essays on this topic -- for example one discussing the ethics of belief, Kant's worries about religious enthusiasm, or epistemic issues that crop up when we think about moral education and autonomy.

Finally, I found it a bit odd that a book so resolutely focused on showing that history can help us think more deeply and creatively about the virtues has little to no discussion of Kant's conception of virtue and all of the good work that has recently been done on that topic. Of course no collection can do it all, and I suppose these desires for more entries in a book that already runs 528 pages just reflect the value that the volume has. This is a large collection, and it could be better unified around a guiding purpose, but I nonetheless think it is surprisingly successful as a whole and that the individual essays should prove useful for both scholars and teachers.

Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.

To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to  upgrade your browser .

Enter the email address you signed up with and we'll email you a reset link.

  • We're Hiring!
  • Help Center

paper cover thumbnail

The Privation Theory of the Vices

Profile image of Sivert Thomas Ellingsen

2019, Filosofisk supplement

Virtues and vices are very widely and naturally regarded as what Aristotle called hexeis – i.e., roughly, as character traits. However, recent empirical findings seem to show that agents rarely or never have or act on hexeis, creating a problem for standard forms of virtue ethics. After surveying the traditional account of hexeis and this recent challenge to it, I sketch out and defend what I call the privation theory of the vices. The privation theory, I argue, allows the virtue ethicist to accept the non-widespreadness of hexeis at a relatively low theoretical cost. More specifically, on the privation theory, the claim that agents rarely instantiate hexeis turns out to be equivalent to a moderate form of pessimism about our current moral situation.

Related Papers

Alexandra Romanyshyn

Following the work of MacIntyre, I call for a particularized approach to ethics. I do not base my argument on concrete situations, but rather, on the way virtue works. Following Aristotle's account, I contend that most people's conception of virtue, even abstracted from particular situations, misses something key: the ways of attaining virtue can be vastly different, and even diametrically opposed, for different people. This difference exists even without differences in external factors. People struggling with divergent vices will need to practice virtue in divergent ways. Therefore, I contend that we need to particularize the way we view the attainment of virtue, not just because each person is in a different situation or context, but because not every person approaches virtue from the same vice.

thesis about vices

The Heythrop Journal

Heather Battaly

Oxford Handbook of Virtue

Pauline Kleingeld

On the basis of psychological research, a group of philosophers known as 'situationists' argue that the evidence belies the existence of broad and stable (or 'global') character traits. They argue that this condemns as psychologically unrealistic those traditions in moral theory in which global virtues are upheld as ideals. After a survey of the debate to date, this article argues that the thesis of situationism is ill-supported by the available evidence. Situationists overlook the explanatory potential of a large class of global character traits, namely, vices that do not involve other-directed malevolence, such as laziness, cowardice, and selfishness. A detailed discussion of the relevant empirical studies bearing on moral psychology shows that the behavioral patterns observed in these studies are consistent with the widespread possession of such non-malicious vices. This means, contrary to the situationist thesis, that the empirical record is fully compatible with the common existence of global character traits.

Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association

In Book II, Chapter 5 of the Nicomachean Ethics Aristotle famously identifies the virtues as hexeis (sing. hexis). Like so many Greek philosophical terms of art, hexis admits of many translations; recent scholarly choices have included “habit,” “disposition,” “state,” “active condition.” In this paper, I argue that some of these translations have tended to obscure the active and causal role that hexeis play in Aristotle’s theory of moral action. This, in turn, has led at least some critics to misunderstand the Aristotelian virtue ethics tradition and mischaracterize virtue ethics as not properly action guiding. Ultimately, seeing the true significance of Aristotle’s claim that the virtues, both moral and intellectual, are hexeis points us towards recognizing just radically different the Aristotelian conception of practical reason and moral action really is in comparison with those typically held by adherents of the alternative theories of normative ethics.

Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy

Robert Weston Siscoe

How demanding is the virtuous life? Can virtue exist alongside hints of vice? Is it possible to be virtuous within a vicious society? A line of thinking running through Diogenes and the Stoics is that even a hint of corruption is inimical to virtue, that participating in a vicious society makes it impossible for a person to be virtuous. One response to this difficulty is to claim that virtue is a threshold concept, that context sets a threshold for what is considered virtuous. On this way of thinking, what counts as virtuous in one society may be more demanding than what passes for virtuous in another. This response seems plausible when considering that virtue-theoretic terms like `honest' are gradable adjectives. Many gradable adjectives, like `long' and `expensive,' have contextual thresholds that shift depending on the situation, and so it is tenable that virtue-theoretic adjectives might function with contextual thresholds as well. A major difficulty for this response, however, is that many virtue terms are absolute gradable adjectives, a variety of gradable adjectives that do not require a contextual threshold. These absolute gradable adjectives instead draw their truth conditions from their maximal degree, suggesting that Diogenes and the Stoics were correct to think that a number of the virtues are incompatible with even a small degree of vice.

Proceedings of the Twentieth World Congress of …

Michael DePaul

Journal of Value Inquiry

Daniel Coren

Using research in social psychology, philosophers such as Gilbert Harman and John Doris argue that human beings do not have – and cannot acquire – character traits such as virtues. Along with defenders of virtue ethics such as Julia Annas and Rachana Kamtekar, they assume that this constitutes a dangerous attack on virtue ethics. I argue that even if virtues and vices did not exist and everyone accepted that truth, (1) we would continue to make attributions of character traits in our ordinary practices and institutions and (2) it would still be useful to strategically harness – rather than suppress or ignore – our virtue (and vice) attributions.

Journal of philosophical Investigations

Journal of Philosophical Investigations

What confers their value on genuine virtues, it is argued, consists in the intrinsic value that instantiating them in thought and action standardly brings about. This granted, virtue theory is argued to be capable of plugging a gap in consequentialist theories of the kind that make actions right which either exemplify optimific practices or are directly optimific. Compliance with optimific practices like truthtelling makes the relevant actions right, subject to certain exceptions. But even if such compliance is combined with the optimificity of beneficent actions, considered singly, that do not exemplify these practices, the resulting theory of rightness remains gap-ridden. The gap can be filled if it is granted that virtuous actions are generally optimific, and this knowledge is incorporated into consequentialist theories of rightness. Thus where no optimific practices are relevant, and no actions are manifestly directly optimific, dispositions of a generally optimific character (virtues) can rightly be adopted.

Loading Preview

Sorry, preview is currently unavailable. You can download the paper by clicking the button above.

RELATED TOPICS

  •   We're Hiring!
  •   Help Center
  • Find new research papers in:
  • Health Sciences
  • Earth Sciences
  • Cognitive Science
  • Mathematics
  • Computer Science
  • Academia ©2024

U.S. flag

An official website of the United States government

The .gov means it’s official. Federal government websites often end in .gov or .mil. Before sharing sensitive information, make sure you’re on a federal government site.

The site is secure. The https:// ensures that you are connecting to the official website and that any information you provide is encrypted and transmitted securely.

  • Publications
  • Account settings

Preview improvements coming to the PMC website in October 2024. Learn More or Try it out now .

  • Advanced Search
  • Journal List
  • Springer Nature - PMC COVID-19 Collection

Logo of phenaturepg

A novel understanding of the nature of epistemic vice

Alkis kotsonis.

School of Education, College of Social Sciences, University of Glasgow, St. Andrews Building, G3 6NH Glasgow, United Kingdom

My aim in this paper is to present and discuss a novel understanding of the nature of epistemic vice. I highlight that epistemic vice such as excessive curiosity, gossip and excessive inquisitiveness do not obstruct the acquisition, transmission and retention of knowledge and are not characterized by a deficiency of epistemic desires or vicious epistemic motivations. However, I argue that such traits ought to be classified as epistemic vices because the agent who possesses them causes epistemic harm to other agents through those traits’ characteristic activities.

To remedy obstructivism’s inability to account for vices that cause epistemic harm in other ways besides blocking effective epistemic inquiry, I propose an amended version of this theory. I argue that epistemic vices are character traits, attitudes, and ways of thinking that obstruct the acquisition, transmission, and retention of knowledge and/or cause other kinds of epistemic harm. In addition, I propose a modified version of motivationalism that cashes out non-obstructing, excess-motivation vices in terms of motivation simply by acknowledging, and incorporating into theory, excessive epistemic drives and the negative epistemic (and non-epistemic) consequences stemming from them.

Introductory remarks

Vice epistemology is the study of the “nature, identity and epistemological significance of intellectual vices” (Cassam, 2016 , p. 159). It involves identifying and analyzing certain character traits, attitudes and/or modes of thinking that can account for imperfect epistemic states (e.g., false beliefs, deficiency of epistemic goods, etc.). One influential approach to the study of epistemic vice 1 is motivationalism which is informed by the responsibilist understanding of the concept of intellectual virtue (see e.g., Code 1984 ; Montmarquet, 1993 ; Zagzebski, 1996 ; Baehr, 2009 , 2011 ). For virtue responsibilists, intellectual virtues (such as open-mindedness and intellectual courage) are characterized by the agent’s strong desire for the acquisition of epistemic goods (e.g., truth and knowledge). Scholars working in motivationalism uphold the inversion thesis according to which vices are the exact opposite of virtues—meaning that they are characterized by imperfect epistemic motivations (see Crerar 2018 , p. 754). For them, intellectual vices stem from a lack of epistemic drives (i.e., one is not interested in acquiring epistemic goods) or even an explicit antagonization of epistemic goods (i.e., one willingly promotes epistemic falsehoods). Scholars such as Zagzebski ( 1996 ), Montmarquet ( 2000 ) and Baehr ( 2010 ) understand intellectual vices as involving motivational defects—i.e., motivations which lack epistemic value either because they are deficient or because they are outright vicious. For example, they maintain that a closed-minded agent is characterized by her lack of epistemic desires or, in some cases, her explicit dislike of epistemic goods.

Scholars such as Cassam ( 2016 , 2019 ) and Crerar ( 2018 ) have recently discussed, contra-motivationalism, examples of epistemic vices which are not characterized by imperfect epistemic motivations. Such examples show that an agent can possess epistemic vices despite having a strong motivation for obtaining epistemic goods. This undermines the motivationalist view on vice and has led Cassam ( 2019 ) to propose a novel view on epistemic vice called obstructivism. Cassam puts forward a consequentialist view on vice and maintains that vices are traits, attitudes, and way of thinking that systematically obstruct the acquisition, transmission, and retention of knowledge (Cassam, 2019 , p. 1). For example, the character trait of closedmindedness is an epistemic vice because of its negative epistemic consequences—it hinders effective epistemic inquiry.

My aim in this paper is to argue that neither the theory of motivationalism nor the theory of obstructivism are broad enough to account for non-obstructing, excess-motivation epistemic vices such as excessive curiosity, gossip, and excessive inquisitiveness. These are traits which do not obstruct the acquisition, transmission, and retention of knowledge (hence non-obstructing) nor involve deficient or vicious epistemic motivations (they are characterized by excess epistemic desires). Nonetheless, I argue that such traits should be classified as epistemic vices since, through their characteristic activities, the agents who possess them come to inflict epistemic harm to other people. To account for such traits, I present and discuss a novel understanding of the nature of epistemic vice: I develop and propose a broadened version of obstructivism which maintains the original theory’s consequentialist nature and incorporates epistemic vices which cause non-obstructing epistemic harm. In addition, I propose a modified version of motivationalism that can cash out non-obstructing, excess-motivation intellectual vices in terms of motivation simply by acknowledging, and incorporating into theory, excessive epistemic drives and the negative epistemic (and non-epistemic) consequences stemming from them.

In what follows (Sect. 2), I begin with a discussion of Cassam’s ( 2016 , 2019 ) and Crerar’s ( 2018 ) arguments against motivationalism and briefly outline Cassam’s ( 2019 ) obstructivism theory. Then, in the third section of this paper, I proceed to discuss excessive curiosity, gossip and excessive inquisitiveness and show that neither obstructivism nor motivationalism can accommodate (in their current form) such non-obstructing, excess-motivation epistemic vices. To remedy this, I then move on in the fourth section of this paper, to develop and propose broader versions of both the theory of obstructivism and the theory of motivationalism that retain the essential characteristics of the original theories while incorporating non-obstructing, excess-motivation epistemic vices under their conceptualization of the term of epistemic vice.

The theory of obstructivism

Scholars who follow the motivationalism viewpoint maintain that intellectual vices “involve non-instrumental motives to oppose, antagonize, or actively avoid things that are epistemically good in themselves” (Tanesini, 2018 , p. 350). For instance, Battaly ( 2017 , p. 5) argues that intellectual vices are “partly composed of bad epistemic motives”. Still, not everyone agrees with the motivationalist view on vice. For instance, Crerar ( 2018 ) has recently discussed the case of Oblomov and provided evidence against what he calls the presence conception of intellectual vice (i.e., the view according to which intellectual vices require the presence of vicious motivations). The Oblomov case shows that one can possess epistemic vice without having vicious epistemic motivations. According to Crerar ( 2018 ), Oblomov possesses the epistemic vices of laziness and incuriosity even though he lacks vicious epistemic motivations—he is simply uninterested in obtaining epistemic goods. Examples such as this show that an explicit antagonization and opposition towards epistemic goods is not a necessary condition for epistemic vice.

Still, most scholars following motivationalism believe that epistemic vices are characterized by a lack of epistemic drives and do not require an explicit antagonization or opposition of epistemic goods (see e.g., Montmarquet 2000 ; Baehr, 2010 ). According to this view, an agent does not need to have bad epistemic motivations to possess epistemic vice—epistemic vice simply presupposes “a lack of desire for knowledge” (Baehr, 2010 , p. 209). This view offers a good enough account of epistemic vices (such as laziness and incuriosity) that are not characterized by vicious motivations.

This view does a competent job at explaining in motivational terms vices such as laziness and incuriosity—i.e., epistemic vices which are not characterized by vicious motivations. Crerar ( 2018 ) calls this motivationalist view (i.e., the view according to which intellectual vices presuppose the absence of good motivations) the absence conception of epistemic vice and discusses the case of Galileo to object to it. Galileo is often depicted in the literature of vice epistemology as a closed-minded individual (see e.g., Roberts and Wood, 2007 , p. 254) and this closemindedness is partly attributed to Galileo’s feelings of intellectual superiority. Galileo’s closemindedness does not involve the presence of vicious epistemic motivations nor the lack of epistemic drives—Galileo was highly motivated in his epistemic pursuits due to his strong desire to acquire epistemic goods. Crerar’s ( 2018 ) discussion of Galileo illustrates that not all epistemic vices are characterized by the absence of good epistemic motivations (or presence of vicious ones).

Still, Crerar ( 2018 ) was not the first to come up with such examples. Before him, Cassam ( 2016 ) had already discussed the case of a conspiracy theorist called Oliver who—despite having strong motivations to acquire the truth—is characterized by his gullibility. Examples such as the ones discussed in this section led Cassam to develop and propose a novel understanding of epistemic vice, one that is similar to Driver’s ( 2001 ) consequentialist view on moral virtue and vice (Cassam, 2019 , p. 11). Cassam argues that epistemic vices are ‘blameworthy, or otherwise reprehensible character traits, attitudes or ways of thinking that systematically obstruct the gaining, keeping or sharing of knowledge’ (Cassam, 2019 , p. 1). For Cassam, the presence of epistemic vice is not conditioned on the agent having imperfect epistemic motivations: “epistemic vices aren’t rooted in a desire for ignorance and needn’t have epistemic motives that account for their badness” (Cassam, 2016 , p. 166). Cassam’s understanding of vice is a consequentialist one. He characterizes epistemic vices in term of their negative consequences for effective epistemic inquiry (Cassam, 2019 , p. 5).

As is evident from his definition of intellectual vice, Cassam does not limit his discussion to character traits (e.g., gullibility, closedmindedness) but expands his understanding of the concept of epistemic vice to include various attitudes (e.g., epistemic prejudice and epistemic malevolence) and ways of thinking (e.g., biased thinking, superstitious thinking). For Cassam, thinking vices are distinct from character vices in that the former are not necessarily part of the latter. For instance, an agent may succumb to closed-minded thinking under certain conditions (e.g., when talking to her mother) but that does not necessarily mean that they possess the vice of closed-mindedness. It may very well be that in the majority of cases (e.g., when she is not talking to her mother) the agent is open-minded. Cassam ( 2019 , p. 56) argues that in order for an agent to possess the trait of closed-mindedness, one needs to consistently engage in closed-minded thinking.

Cassam also discusses epistemic attitudes as a kind of intellectual vice and notes that attitudes “are orientations or postures towards something” ( 2019 , p. 13). For him, epistemic attitudes and character traits are closely related but distinct. To distinguish between attitudes and traits, Cassam ( 2019 , p. 98) notes that “it makes perfect sense to suppose that a person might display a particular attitude in response to a particular question even if they lack the corresponding character trait; their attitude in this case might be out of character”. For instance, the fact that one might exhibit an intellectually arrogant attitude in a given scenario or epistemic domain does not necessarily entail that they possess the character trait of arrogance. It could be that they have an intellectually arrogant attitude only under certain circumstances. One of Cassam’s ( 2019 , p. 94) own examples is the arrogant attitude of certain senior members of the Bush administration that “prevented them from coming to know how many troops would be needed in Iraq”.

Non-obstructing, excess-motivation epistemic vices

Excessive curiosity, gossip and excessive inquisitiveness.

In this section, I proceed to present examples of epistemic vices which do not obstruct effective epistemic inquiry (hence are non-obstructing) nor involve deficient or vicious epistemic motivations. I discuss the cases of (i) excessive curiosity, (ii) gossiping and (iii) excessive inquisitiveness and argue that traits such as these should be classified as epistemic vices due to their negative epistemic consequences 2 . Through the characteristic activities of these epistemic vices, agents cause epistemic harm to other people 3 .

Epistemic harm has a central role in my understanding of the concept of epistemic vice. The kind of epistemic vices discussed in this section are characterized by the epistemic harm that the agent inflicts to other agents through those vices’ characteristic activities. Following Cassam’s ( 2019 ) conception of vice, I argue that such traits are intellectual vices because of the negative epistemic consequences they bring about. My discussion is informed by Fricker’s ( 2007 ) understanding of epistemic injustice. Fricker develops the concept of epistemic injustice to classify cases of injustice that are distinctively of an epistemic kind. For her, epistemic injustice “consisting, most fundamentally, in a wrong done to someone specifically in their capacity as a knower” (Fricker, 2007 , p. 1) 4 . In her 2007 book titled ‘ Epistemic Injustice: Power and the Ethics of Knowledge ’, Fricker identifies two kinds of epistemic injustice: (a) testimonial injustice and (b) hermeneutical injustice. Briefly put, testimonial injustice occurs when a hearer does not give the appropriate credence to a speaker’s word (and hence the speaker is wronged in their capacity as a knower—Fricker 2007 , p. 10) and hermeneutical injustice occurs when one cannot make sense of their social experiences due to “prejudicial flaws in shared resources for social interpretation” and hence prevents the knower from understanding and communicating their experiences (Fricker, 2007 , p. 148) 5 . Building on Fricker’s work on epistemic injustice, scholars have identified and explained various kinds of epistemic injustice such as epistemic oppression (Dotson, 2014 ), silencing (McGlynn, 2019 ) and epistemic injustice in utterance interpretation (Peet, 2017 ). In the remainder of this subsection, I proceed to describe the epistemic vices of excess curiosity, gossip and excess inquisitiveness and illustrate how they relate to the concept of epistemic injustice.

Virtue responsibilists have categorized curiosity as an intellectual virtue (see e.g., Baehr 2011 , pp. 19–21; Turri et al., 2017 ; Ross 2020 ). For instance, Ross ( 2020 , p. 116) defines the intellectual virtue of curiosity as a character trait involving “the disposition to experience appropriately discerning, exacting and timely curiosity, motivated by a non-instrumental appreciation of epistemic goods”. I understand excessive curiosity as the corresponding excess-motivation vice of curiosity. Excess curiosity is an epistemic vice characterized by a lack of epistemic restraint (Manson, 2012 ). Consider, for example, the case of John. Being excessively curious, John does not hesitate to open the mail of his neighbors whenever the opportunity arises. To make matters worse, due to his unlimited ‘thirst’ for information, John is motivated to actively intercept the mails of his neighbors. He does not simply open the mail of other people whenever such letters find their way to him, but he actively seeks to intercept the letters of other people and read them before they reach their intended recipient. In other words, John is not able to restrain his epistemic desires even when they drive him to burden and/or cause harm to others. One’s personal correspondence could contain all sort of personal information. Mary might be expecting the results of her latest health check-up while Jack might be waiting for his tax records and bank statement. Having read their letters, John has obtained personal information about his neighbors without their consent. He has come to possess sensitive information which he was not warranted to obtain. Hence, he has caused epistemic harm to his neighbors—he has inflicted an injustice of an epistemic kind. He has undermined their right to privacy of information 6 .

Neither motivationalism nor obstructivism can account as to why excessive curiosity should be classified as an epistemic vice. The above example shows that excessive curiosity is not an epistemic vice due to a lack of epistemic desires or vicious epistemic motivations. John does not oppose or antagonize epistemic goods. Once he intercepts and reads the mail of his neighbors, he passes it on to them acting as if he has not read it. He does not deprive his neighbors of their mail—he simply reads it before they do. His actions stem from his strong epistemic desires 7 . Also, John’s excessive curiosity which leads him to read his neighbor’s mail does not obstruct the gaining, keeping, and/or sharing of epistemic goods. On the contrary, it seems to be conducive to the sharing of knowledge—if John were not overly curious, he would not actively seek to acquire information about his neighbors.

Gossip is another example of a non-obstructing, excess-motivation kind of intellectual vice (for more on the intellectual vice of gossip see Kotsonis 2021 ). Gossip involves the verbal transaction between two agents concerning a third agent with the sole purpose of acquiring ‘juicy’ information about the target’s personal life 8 . The disposition to gossip is an acquired character trait (i.e., one is a gossiper). Through gossip the agent comes to acquire epistemic goods which they are not warranted to possess. They come to violate the right of privacy of information of other people. Consider, for example, the case of Nick. Nick is an excellent gossiper—he is both epistemically motivated and competent in the activity of gossiping. Through gossiping with Andreas, who was in the past romantically involved with Nick’s boss Stephan, Nick acquires the truth about his boss’s love affairs (e.g., their choice of partners). In addition, through gossiping with Andreas, Nick also comes to learn the truth about Stephan’s financial situation (i.e., that he is rich) and mental health issues (i.e., that he suffers from panic attacks) 9 .

Gossip is neither attributable to imperfect epistemic motivations nor does it obstruct the acquisition, transmission, and retention of knowledge. The agent who possesses this trait is motivated to acquire epistemic goods through gossip and values those epistemic goods for their own sake (e.g., does not have some ulterior non-epistemic motivation for engaging in acts of gossip). In addition, through the activity characteristic of gossip, the excellent gossiper is in a position to acquire epistemic goods which would not be accessible to him through other means. Of course, one does not necessarily engage in acts of gossip out of their desire to acquire epistemic goods. For instance, one may engage in idle gossip to blend in with a group of people. However, for the purposes of this paper, I narrow my discussion to acts of gossip ultimately aiming at the acquisition of epistemic goods (i.e., acquiring ‘juicy’ information about another agent).

Besides gossip and excess curiosity, excess inquisitiveness is also another example of a non-obstructing, excess motivation epistemic vice. Watson ( 2015 ) has recently characterized inquisitiveness and accordingly classified it as a responsibilist kind of virtue. According to Watson ( 2015 , p. 277), the agent who possesses the virtue of inquisitiveness is “characteristically motivated to engage sincerely in good questioning”. In other words, when one possesses the virtue of inquisitiveness, one has the competency to engage in good questioning whenever this is epistemically appropriate. I understand excessive inquisitiveness as the excess-motivation vice of the virtue of inquisitiveness. Due to their inability to exercise epistemic restraint, the agent who possesses excessive inquisitiveness has the disposition to engage in excessive questioning.

Consider the following example of excessive inquisitiveness: Gale, who is characterized by her disposition to engage in excessive questioning, has dinner with her best friend Harry and his new partner James. During dinner, and because of her tendency for excessive questioning that is characterized by a lack of epistemic restraint, Gale asks Harry several personal questions. Her questions are of such nature and phrased in such manner that they reveal things about Harry’s personal life—things that James was not aware of. These are things that Harry would not like to discuss with him at this point in their relationship. Imagine, for example, that she asks him whether he has any news regarding his latest health checkup and health problems. Or imagine that she asks him about his sister and the terrible relationship he has with her. Also, imagine that because Gale is his best friend and because he is kind-hearted, Harry responds to her questions—albeit in a rather reluctant and evasive manner. Still, Gale acquires epistemic goods through her excessive questioning—she learns about Harry’s health condition and the latest news about his relationship with his sister. Nonetheless, she has caused epistemic harm to her friend. Her inability to restrain her epistemic desire to acquire epistemic goods through persistent questioning has forced Harry to unwilling self-disclosure in the presence of his partner, James.

The vice of excessive inquisitiveness does not originate from imperfect epistemic motivations. On the contrary, Gale is strongly motivated to engage in questioning because of her strong epistemic desires. For example, she has a strong desire to know about Harry’s health condition. Also, excessive inquisitiveness does not obstruct the acquisition, transmission, and retention of knowledge. Through the characteristic activity of this vice, Gale is able to acquire certain epistemic goods. It could even be argued that Gale’s disposition for excessive questioning is also the reason that James has acquired certain truths about his partner Harry.

Perhaps one could argue that the structure of the above example is unique and that in most circumstances excessive questioning does not cause epistemic harm to other agents. However, I maintain that if one has the tendency for excessive questioning that is characterized by a lack of epistemic restraint and consideration for context, sooner or later they are going to cause epistemic (and potentially also non-epistemic) harm to other agents. Imagine, for example, a student who keeps asking her professor personal questions during lecture time. Also consider the case of Donald who decides to watch a movie with a friend who will not stop asking him questions about unrelated matters—Donald is bound to miss the opportunity to acquire certain information. Lastly, consider the case of Christin who, due to her excessive questioning, keeps distracting Helen from quietly reading her philosophy papers 10 .

Non-obstructing, excessive-motivation epistemic vices: discussing objections

One could object to my argument that excessive curiosity, gossip, and excessive inquisitiveness should be classified as epistemic vice. As already noted, they do not entail imperfect epistemic motivations, nor do they obstruct the acquisition, retention, and transmission of epistemic goods. Hence, one could maintain that the theories of motivationalism and obstructivism cannot be used to identify them as epistemic vices simply because such traits are not vices of the intellect.

But assuming that they are not epistemic vices, how should then one classify traits such as excessive curiosity, gossip, and excessive inquisitiveness? Perhaps one could attempt to make the case that such qualities are characterized by moral instead of epistemic failings. One could argue that the trait of excessive curiosity can lead one to act in ways that are considered immoral. For instance, John is doing something morally wrong when he intercepts his neighbor’s correspondence. Also, the kind of gossip I am discussing in this paper involves the violation of norms by the speaker: they speak about topics that are considered taboo. Hence, one could argue that there is something morally wrong in talking about another person’s private life behind their back. Lastly, one could argue that excessive inquisitiveness involves acts which are morally wrong. For example, Gale, through her insistent questions, is verbally harassing Harry.

First, in reply to such an objection, one could highlight the fact that scholars who work in virtue responsibilism are reluctant to argue in favor of a sharp distinction between intellectual virtues/vices and moral ones. For example, Zagzebski ( 1996 , p. 158) notes that we do not have any reason for categorizing intellectual virtues and moral virtues as distinct. Roberts and Wood ( 2007 , p. 180) maintain that no strict line can be drawn between intellectual and moral virtues and Baehr ( 2011 ) argues that intellectual and moral virtues are not mutually exclusive 11 . In agreement, I argue that moral and intellectual virtues are not clearly distinguishable. They are quite similar both in their nature and the manner in which agents come to acquire them. Both intellectual and moral virtues involve handling of feelings, proper understanding of the world and a degree of voluntariness (for more on this point, see Zagzebski 1996 ). In addition, they are both acquired through imitation and habituation. There are even some virtues, such as courage and humility, that have “both moral and intellectual forms” (Zagzebski, 1996 , p. 159). Therefore, as Watson ( 2015 , p. 280) rightly argues, since moral and intellectual virtues cannot clearly be distinguished then it is only to be expected that cases of intellectual vices can be cashed out in terms of moral vices as well. In other words, the fact that the examples of excess-vices discussed in this paper can also be understood in terms of moral vices does not constitute an objection to my arguments.

However, this might not provide a satisfactory answer to some who would push on with the idea that the kind of epistemic vice that I discuss in this paper is better understood in terms of non-epistemic consequences. To answer this, following Cassam’s ( 2019 ) consequentialist understanding of epistemic vice, I maintain that such traits primarily qualify as epistemic vices because they are fundamentally characterized by the negative epistemic consequences which they systematically bring about (although they are not of the kind of epistemic consequences that Cassam has in mind when proposing the theory of obstructivism). Therefore, in a sense, they fall under the theory of obstructivism when such theory is broadly understood as conceptualizing epistemic vices in terms of their negative epistemic consequences.

As already pointed out, there is an injustice of an epistemic kind systematically inflicted through the characteristic activities of these traits. All three epistemic vices discussed in this paper stem from a lack of epistemic restraint—and this lack of epistemic restraint is the reason that the agents who possess these traits cannot control their epistemic desires and end up causing epistemic harm to other agents (e.g., acquiring and/or revealing their personal information without their consent 12 , 13 ). The harm caused is epistemic, as opposed to non-epistemic, because the harm is knower-initiated (i.e., caused by the knower to another agent the moment the knower comes to acquire epistemic goods), involves epistemic goods (someone’s private information) and the agent who suffers the epistemic injustice is harmed in their capacity as a knower (they are deprived of the choice to be the sole knower of their personal information and disclose them only to whomever and whenever they desire/deem fit) 14 . This fits well with Pohlhaus’ viewpoint on epistemic injustice according to which epistemic injustice not only “wrongs a knower as a knower, but also is a wrong that a knower perpetrates as a knower” (Pohlhaus, 2017 , p. 14). Note also that the epistemic harm caused by the characteristic activities of these traits does not hinge on the infliction of non-epistemic harm. For instance, in the example of excessive curiosity discussed previously, John causes epistemic harm (when he opens his neighbor’s letters) independently of whether he use the information he acquires to cause further harm (as for example if he uses it for extortion). He causes epistemic harm to them the moment he reads their personal correspondence and obtains information about their personal life without their consent. If John decides to let everyone know that Jack has a lot of money, he may also cause non-epistemic harm to him. People, for example, might start asking Jack for a loan and begrudging him when he does not give them one. However, even though John may decide not to do anything with the information he obtains, his excessive curiosity has caused epistemic harm.

Some may have objections to my characterization of excessive curiosity, gossip, and excessive inquisitiveness as epistemic vices, even when they bear the fruit of knowledge. Consider, for instance, the following case: A scientist has an overweening urge to learn the truth. This leads them to invade the privacy of their colleagues, reading their results. As a result of their obsessive inquiry, the scientist makes an epochal breakthrough in her understanding of the universe. Acknowledging the great epistemic benefits that flowed from their snooping, does the scientist really display epistemic vice in reading their colleagues’ results, simply because she has invaded their privacy? Indeed, one could argue that the epistemic benefits of the scientist’s snooping outweigh the harms. Still, I maintain that this does not undo the fact that they are displaying an epistemic vice: they have caused epistemic harm to their colleagues by invading their privacy without their consent. The kind of traits that I am discussing in this paper are fundamentally characterized by the epistemic harm which they systematically bring about, and the fact that there are some extreme cases in which the positive results might outweigh the harms does not undo my overall argument. Similarly, one could come up with cases in which (due to some stroke of luck) vices such as gullibility, dogmatism, epistemic cowardliness, and carelessness bring about positive epistemic outcomes. Still, following obstructivism, this does not mean that we should not categorize such traits as epistemic vices. It remains that in the vast majority of cases these traits will obstruct the gaining, keeping or sharing of knowledge.

Perhaps one could take one step back and instead argue (against my view) that the traits discussed in this paper are not vices of any kind. In the previous paragraph, I highlighted how the traits discussed in this paper can be classified under Cassam’s ( 2019 ) broad consequentialist understanding of epistemic vice—the agent who possesses such traits systematically causes epistemic harm to other agents through the characteristic activities of these traits. This also relates to Foot’s ( 1978 ) Neo-Aristotelian conception of virtue and vice. According to Foot ( 1978 ), virtues are beneficial characteristics that an agent needs to possess for both her sake and those around her. Correspondingly, following Foot’s conceptualization of virtue, one could conceive of vices as those traits that systematically cause harm to the agent and/or others. Hence, excessive curiosity, gossip and excessive inquisitiveness should be classified as (epistemic) vices since they clearly cause (epistemic) harm to those around the agent.

Altering the theories of obstructivism and motivationalism

In this section, I propose ways in which the theories of motivationalism and obstructivism can be altered in such a manner as to account for non-obstructing, excess-motivation vices. I begin by discussing obstructivism and argue that the theory’s understanding of harmful epistemic consequences can be broadened to include non-obstructing negative epistemic consequences. I then proceed to discuss motivationalism and propose a way in which the theory can be expanded to include imperfect epistemic motivations of an excessive kind.

Obstructivism and non-obstructing epistemic vices

As already noted, Cassam ( 2019 ) puts forward a consequentialist view on vice. For him, vices “systematically obstruct the gaining, keeping or sharing of knowledge” (Cassam, 2019 , p. 1). However, none of the epistemic vices discussed in the previous section bring about such kind of negative epistemic consequences. Excessive curiosity, gossip and excessive inquisitiveness do not systematically obstruct the gaining, keeping, and/or sharing of knowledge. On the contrary, they are all conducive to effective epistemic inquiry—i.e., the agent who possesses these traits is in a better epistemic position to acquire epistemic goods than the agent who lacks such qualities 15 . Hence, as already discussed, obstructivism (in its current form) does not account for the kind of epistemic vice discussed in the previous section.

Still, in this short subsection, I want to point out that with some theoretical alterations the theory of obstructivism can easily incorporate non-obstructing epistemic vices under its understanding of the concept of vice. As it has been already noted, in its broader version, obstructivism upholds that all intellectual vices are to be understood in terms of the negative epistemic consequences they bring about. Expanding on Cassam’s ( 2019 ) obstructivism theory, one could argue that epistemic vices are character traits, epistemic attitudes, and ways of thinking that systematically obstruct the acquisition, transmission, and retention of knowledge and/or cause other kinds of epistemic harm . A more general phrasing of this version would be the following: epistemic vices are character traits, attitudes, or ways of thinking that systematically cause epistemic harm to the agent who possesses them and/or other agents.

This version of obstructivism retains all (or at least most) essential characteristics of Cassam’s ( 2019 ) view on vice and accounts for those epistemic vices which the original version is not broad enough to include. Let us briefly consider how, when broadened in this manner, the theory of obstructivism accommodates for non-obstructing, excess-motivation epistemic vices. Excessive curiosity, gossip and excessive inquisitiveness are blameworthy, or otherwise reprehensible qualities because of their negative epistemic consequences. Although they do not obstruct the acquisition and retention of knowledge, they nonetheless cause other kinds of epistemic harm. The agents who possess such traits cause epistemic harm to other people through the characteristic activities of these vices.

One might point out that the way I have defined epistemic vice does not justify me in presenting this altered view as an obstructivist one. It is true that calling obstructivist a viewpoint which includes non-obstructing vices is counterintuitive. Perhaps it would be better to go back to a more generic description and describe this view on vice as epistemic consequentialism. This would reflect that epistemic vices are characterized by their negative epistemic consequences (which are not limited to knowledge-obstruction). Still, irrespectively of how one calls this new version, the most fundamental aspects of Cassam’s ( 2019 ) obstructivist view remain. For example, similarly to the original version of the theory, this new version upholds that epistemic vices (1) are not limited to traits but include various attitudes and ways of thinking, (2) are characterized by their negative epistemic consequences, (3) do not require vicious and/or deficient motivational states and (4) reflect badly on the agent and the agent can be criticized for possessing them (Cassam, 2019 , pp. 22–23).

Motivationalism and excess-motivation vices

Unlike obstructivism, perhaps it can be insisted that (in its current form) motivationalism can account for excess-motivation virtues. As already noted, motivationalism is the view according to which all kinds of epistemic vices are attributable to motivations which lack epistemic value either because they are deficient or because they are outright vicious. Hence, one could put forward the idea that excessive curiosity, gossip and/or excessive inquisitiveness are characterized by a lack of epistemic motivation, a motivation which does not perceive epistemic goods as goods in themselves and/or even an explicit dislike for epistemic goods. Nonetheless, I do not believe that this is the case for either of these three vices. As shown in Sect. 3, the agents who possess the vices of excessive curiosity, gossip and/or excessive inquisitiveness are motivated to act out of their desire for epistemic goods. None of these virtues require that the agent is motivated by imperfect epistemic desires (at least not in the way motivationalism currently understands imperfect motivational states, i.e., as involving either deficient epistemic drives or vicious ones). Hence, it seems safe to conclude that (in its current form) motivationalism does not account for the kind of epistemic vices discussed in this paper 16 .

Nonetheless, I want to highlight the fact that motivationalism has a way to explain vices such as excessive curiosity, gossip and excess inquisitiveness in terms of imperfect epistemic motivations—the agent who possesses these vices lacks epistemic restraint and hence their epistemic desires become unregulated and excessive (in the sense that they cause epistemic harm) 17 . However, to support such view, the theory of motivationalism will need to be altered in such a manner as to include excessive epistemic desires as cases of imperfect epistemic motivations. The way that motivationalism is currently developed in the literature of vice epistemology does not allow room for cases of excessive epistemic desires. For example, Montmarquet ( 2000 , pp. 138–139) understands intellectual vices as involving a lack of epistemic effort, Baehr ( 2010 ) puts forward the idea that epistemic vices are characterized by the agent’s lack of epistemic drives and Tanesini ( 2018 , p. 350) maintains that “intellectual character vices involve non instrumental motives to oppose, antagonise, or avoid things that are epistemically good in themselves”.

In order to characterize the vices that I have discussed in this paper in terms of motivation, one would first have to accept that there is such a thing as epistemic desires of an excessive kind. One might be inclined to argue (against my view) that epistemic desires can never be of an excessive nature- and uphold that the stronger the epistemic desires one has, the better 18 . The following example is a good way to illustrate the existence of excessive epistemic desires and the negative epistemic (and non-epistemic) consequences stemming from such desires. Nicol is an exceptionally capable person when it comes to epistemic pursuits. She is smart and driven in her epistemic endeavors. Still, Nicol has also a strong desire to acquire the truth about various conspiracy theories—her desire is so strong that it could even be understood as an obsession 19 . Because of this obsession (and the time and effort she puts into trying to find the truth), she drops out of college, ends up having no friends, rarely sees her family and lives below the poverty line. Had Nicol being less interested in acquiring the truth, she would be living a much better life (which would also perhaps allow her to acquire more epistemic goods than she does now—e.g., by going to college). On top of that, because of her excessive epistemic desires, Nicol causes epistemic harm to other agents. For example, believing that her neighbors are spies, she comes to intercept and read their personal correspondence.

Assuming that my overall argument in this paper stands (i.e., that current versions of motivationalism cannot account for the epistemic vices of excess curiosity, gossip and excess inquisitiveness), scholars working in motivationalism have two main options: (i) bite the bullet, (ii) alter motivationalism so as to incorporate such epistemic vices. In this short subsection, I have tried to flesh out what the latter response might look like 20 .

Concluding remarks

My aim in this paper has been to present and discuss a novel understanding of the nature of epistemic vice. I argued that there are certain epistemic vices (i.e., excess curiosity, gossip and excess inquisitiveness) of a non-obstructing excess-motivation kind, that neither the theory of motivationalism nor the theory of obstructivism are broad enough to include under their conceptualization of the term of intellectual vice. Throughout this paper, I illustrated how these vices relate to the concept of epistemic harm and characterized them both in terms of negative epistemic consequences and excessive epistemic motivations. To remedy for the inability of motivationalism and obstructivism to account for such vices, I developed and proposed broader versions that retain the essential characteristics of these theories and include non-obstructing, excess-motivation epistemic vices under their understanding of the concept of intellectual vice.

Conflict of interest

The author declares that they have no conflict of interest.

1 Throughout this paper, I use the terms ‘intellectual virtue’ and ‘epistemic virtue’ as well as the terms ‘intellectual vice’ and ‘epistemic vice’ interchangeably.

2 I should note that although I identify such epistemic vices as traits, I follow Cassam’s ( 2019 ) conceptualization of epistemic vice in that I believe that excess curiosity, gossiping and excess inquisitiveness can also be understood in terms of epistemic attitudes and/or modes of thinking. For instance, one’s attitude and/or way of thinking could be characterized as a gossiping one—i.e., characterized by a desire to acquire ‘juicy’ information (e.g., choice of sex partners) about another person behind their back.

3 This relates to the concept of violence (which can be understood as including non-physical harm) and the view that violence is inevitably intertwined with morality—see Magnani 2011 .

4 Later in this section, I will be formulating arguments that rely on a reverse version of Fricker’s ( 2007 ) conception of epistemic injustice. According to this reverse version, there are cases of epistemic injustice in which the knower inflicts epistemic harm to other people.

5 Fricker’s ( 2007 ) analysis of epistemic injustice is not without its critics. For instance, Maitra ( 2010 , p. 210) has argued that the two kinds of epistemic injustice discussed by Fricker “are more similar than she allows”.

6 For more on a person’s right to privacy of information, see the principles of information privacy as well as privacy laws (e.g., EU’s General Data Protection Regulation and the Data Protection Directive). It is the kind of information protected by such laws that I am referring to here.

7 Ross ( 2020 , p. 116) argues that “an agent’s curiosity will be virtuous…to the extent that it is non-instrumentally motivated by their appreciation of epistemic goods”. John’s curiosity satisfies this condition: he is motivated to act out of his love for epistemic goods. His curiosity does not involve deficient or vicious epistemic motivations.

8 According to Robinson ( 2016 ), there are two different kinds of gossip: (i) evaluative and (ii)idle. The former involves normative evaluations of the target of gossip (e.g., George is a cheater, Mary is dishonest), while the latter does not. In addition, both kinds of gossip are characterized by a violation of norms. In the case of evaluative gossip, the subject of gossip has violated a certain set of norms (e.g., moral norms, cultural norms) while in the case of idle gossip it is the gossiper that violates norms by talking about topics which are considered taboo (e.g., talking about his boss’s sex life). For more on the topic of gossip, see also Lind et al., ( 2007 ), Bertolotti & Magnani ( 2014 ), and Alfano & Robinson ( 2017 ). Note that Robinson ( 2016 ) and Alfano & Robinson ( 2017 ) focus on evaluative gossip, while in this paper I am focusing on idle gossip which ultimately aims at the acquisition of ‘juicy’ information about the personal life of the subject.

9 One may point out that gossip is often unreliable. However, the excellent gossiper is, in the vast majority of cases, in a position to judge when one of their interlocutors is lying to them. After all, being themselves an excellent gossiper, they are aware of the fact that information acquired via gossip can often be unreliable and hence are always careful to double-check them (e.g., by gossiping about the same piece of information with other agents).

10 Perhaps one could argue that some of these cases can be understood in obstructivist terms. For instance, in the film example, one’s excessive questioning can obstruct another agent’s acquisition of knowledge. Still, the problem is that obstructivism accounts only for some of these cases. As already noted, for example, in Gale’s case there is on obstruction of epistemic inquiry. Hence, as I will argue in section IV, the scope of obstructivism needs to be broadened in order to account for all kinds of epistemic harm inflicted by vices such as excessive inquisitiveness (and not simply epistemic harms of an obstructing nature).

11 Note that my discussion at this point has been greatly informed by Watson’s ( 2015 ) discussion of how contemporary virtue scholars understand the relation between moral and intellectual virtues.

12 All three traits trample on the notion of privacy of information. Still, it should be noted that the agents who possess these traits are not motivated to act out of a desire to cause epistemic harm (violate a person’s right) but out of their desire to acquire epistemic goods—i.e., their actions originate from good epistemic motivations.

13 Some might point out that one’s right to privacy of information should be understood as an ethical right. Still, this does not necessarily preclude us from understanding the violation of this right as bringing about epistemic harm. I have argued that the harm caused is epistemic, as opposed to non-epistemic, because the harm is knower-initiated (i.e., caused by the knower to another agent the moment the knower comes to acquire epistemic goods), involves epistemic goods (one’s private information) and the agent is wronged qua knower (they are deprived of the choice to be the sole knower of their personal information and disclose them whenever they themselves desire/deem fit).

14 One might argue that these conditions are not sufficient since they seem to suggest that blackmail is an epistemic harm: it is knower-initiated and involves epistemic goods. Still, I maintain that blackmail does not fit the description. Blackmail requires coming to acquire another agent’s private information (and sometimes not even that—one could bluff) without (or even with) their consent and then explicitly using this information to gain some benefit (which may or may not be of epistemic nature and in most cases isn’t). In the cases I discuss in this paper, agents do not need to use the information they obtain (in any way) for epistemic harm to take place—epistemic harm occurs the moment they acquire another agent’s information without their consent and the harm caused does not hinge on any additional actions and/or consequences.

15 The discussion can be expanded to include thinking vices (Cassam, 2019 ); and traditional “fallacies” that have positive cognitive value (Woods, 2013 ; Magnani, 2015 ).

16 To be fair, Battaly ( 2010 ) has discussed cases of excessive epistemic desires and has linked them to epistemic vice. Still, it seems that she is one of the very few scholars to have made this connection. Most scholars following the motivationalism viewpoint are either reluctant to accept that there is such a thing as excessive epistemic desires or have not considered it as a possibility (for more information, see the next paragraph and footnote 13).

17 To give an example, the vice of excessive curiosity can be understood as involving unregulated and excessive epistemic drives, while the virtue of curiosity can be understood as involving restraint, regulation, and control of epistemic desires on the part of the agent.

18 For instance, Zagzebski ( 1996 , pp. 196–197) seems somewhat reluctant to attribute vices such as the ones discussed in this paper to an excessive motivation to know since she believes that such motivation is not a defect and does not necessarily give rise to vice. Also, Code (1987, pp. 44–45) may be hesitant to attribute “intellectual virtue to the voracious collector of facts” but still, her hesitancy does not stem from the belief that epistemic desires can be of an excessive nature but from the view that “it is possible, theoretically at least, to know everything, yet understand nothing”.

19 One could argue that what is wrong with agents such as Nicol is not that they care about epistemic goods too much but that they care about the wrong things. However, this does not sound right. Being motivated to find out the truth about things such as the JFK assassination, 9/11 and the Covid-19 pandemic is not caring about the wrong things—some of these events have had a tremendous impact on our lives.

20 It might also be worthwhile to note that the idea that there are both excessive and deficient levels of epistemic motivations fits well with the Aristotelian conception of the golden mean (see, e.g. EN , 1107a). For Aristotle, virtue lies in a mean between two vices and since virtues and vices are partly constituted of motivations, the idea that motivational states admit to both excess and deficiency seems to follow. This might be of some sway for scholars (working in motivationalism) who maintain that they build their conceptions of intellectual vice based on Aristotle’s conceptualization of the term (see e.g., Zagzebski 1996 ; Battaly, 2014 , 2017 ).

Publisher’s note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

  • Alfano M, Robinson B. Gossip as a burdened virtue. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice. 2017; 20 :473–487. doi: 10.1007/s10677-017-9809-y. [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Baehr J. Evidentialism, vice, and virtue. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. 2009; 78 :545–567. doi: 10.1111/j.1933-1592.2009.00255.x. [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Baehr J. Epistemic malevolence. In: Battaly H, editor. Virtue and vice: Moral and epistemic. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell; 2010. pp. 189–213. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Baehr J. The inquiring mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2011. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Battaly H. Epistemic self-indulgence. Metaphilosophy. 2010; 41 :214–234. doi: 10.1111/j.1467-9973.2009.01619.x. [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Battaly H. Varieties of epistemic vice. In: Matheson J, Vitz R, editors. The ethics of belief. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2014. pp. 51–75. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Battaly H. Testimonial injustice, epistemic vice, and vice epistemology. In: Kidd I, Medina J, Pohlhaus G, editors. The Routledge handbook of epistemic injustice. London: Routledge Press; 2017. pp. 223–231. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Bertolotti T, Magnani L. An epistemological analysis of gossip and gossip-based knowledge. Synthese. 2014; 191 :4037–4067. doi: 10.1007/s11229-014-0514-2. [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Cassam Q. Vice epistemology. The Monist. 2016; 99 :159–180. doi: 10.1093/monist/onv034. [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Cassam Q. Vices of the mind: From the intellectual to the political. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2019. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Code L. Toward a responsibilist epistemology. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. 1984; 45 :29–50. doi: 10.2307/2107325. [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Crerar C. Motivational approaches to intellectual vice. Australasian Journal of Philosophy. 2018; 96 :753–766. doi: 10.1080/00048402.2017.1394334. [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Dotson K. Conceptualizing epistemic oppression. Social Epistemology. 2014; 28 :115–138. doi: 10.1080/02691728.2013.782585. [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Driver J. Uneasy virtue. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; 2001. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Foot P. Virtues and vices and other essays in moral philosophy. Oxford: Blackwell; 1978. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Fricker M. Epistemic injustice: Power and the ethics of knowing. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2007. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Kotsonis, A. (2021). The curious case of the excellent gossiper. Philosophia . 10.1007/s11406-021-00444-1 [ CrossRef ]
  • Lind PG, Silva D, Andrade LR, Herrmann HJ. Spreading gossip in social networks. Physical Review E. 2007; 76 :036117. doi: 10.1103/PhysRevE.76.036117. [ PubMed ] [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Magnani L. Understanding violence: The intertwining of morality, religion, and violence: A philosophical stance. Berlin: Springer; 2011. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Magnani L. Naturalizing logic: Errors of reasoning vindicated: Logic reapproaches cognitive science. Journal of Applied Logic. 2015; 13 :13–26. doi: 10.1016/j.jal.2014.11.001. [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Maitra I. The nature of epistemic injustice. Philosophical Books. 2010; 51 :195–211. doi: 10.1111/j.1468-0149.2010.00511.x. [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Manson N. Epistemic restraint and the vice of curiosity. Philosophy. 2012; 87 :239–259. doi: 10.1017/S0031819112000046. [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • McGlynn A. Testimonial injustice, pornography, and silencing. Analytic Philosophy. 2019; 60 :405–417. doi: 10.1111/phib.12152. [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Montmarquet J. Epistemic virtue and doxastic responsibility. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield; 1993. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Montmarquet J. An ‘internalist’ conception of virtue. In: Axtell G, editor. Knowledge, belief, and character: Readings in virtue epistemology. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield; 2000. pp. 135–148. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Peet A. Epistemic injustice in utterance interpretation. Synthese. 2017; 194 :3421–3443. doi: 10.1007/s11229-015-0942-7. [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Pohlhaus G. Varieties of epistemic injustice. In: Kidd I, Medina J, Pohlhaus G, editors. The Routledge handbook of epistemic injustice. London: Routledge Press; 2017. pp. 13–26. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Robert R, Woods WJ. Intellectual virtues: An essay in regulative epistemology. Oxford: Clarendon Press; 2007. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Robinson B. Character, caricature, and gossip. The Monist. 2016; 99 :198–211. doi: 10.1093/monist/onv036. [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Ross L. The virtue of curiosity. Episteme. 2020; 17 :105–120. doi: 10.1017/epi.2018.31. [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Tanesini A. Epistemic vice and motivation. Metaphilosophy. 2018; 49 :350–367. doi: 10.1111/meta.12301. [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Turri, J., Alfano, M., & Greco, J. (2017). Virtue epistemology. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy , https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/epistemology-virtue/
  • Watson L. What is inquisitiveness. American Philosophical Quarterly. 2015; 52 :273–288. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Woods J. Errors of reasoning. Naturalizing the logic of inference. London: College Publications; 2013. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Zagzebski L. Virtues of the mind: An inquiry into the nature of virtue and the ethical foundations of knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; 1996. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Search Menu

Sign in through your institution

  • Browse content in Arts and Humanities
  • Browse content in Archaeology
  • Anglo-Saxon and Medieval Archaeology
  • Archaeological Methodology and Techniques
  • Archaeology by Region
  • Archaeology of Religion
  • Archaeology of Trade and Exchange
  • Biblical Archaeology
  • Contemporary and Public Archaeology
  • Environmental Archaeology
  • Historical Archaeology
  • History and Theory of Archaeology
  • Industrial Archaeology
  • Landscape Archaeology
  • Mortuary Archaeology
  • Prehistoric Archaeology
  • Underwater Archaeology
  • Urban Archaeology
  • Zooarchaeology
  • Browse content in Architecture
  • Architectural Structure and Design
  • History of Architecture
  • Residential and Domestic Buildings
  • Theory of Architecture
  • Browse content in Art
  • Art Subjects and Themes
  • History of Art
  • Industrial and Commercial Art
  • Theory of Art
  • Biographical Studies
  • Byzantine Studies
  • Browse content in Classical Studies
  • Classical History
  • Classical Philosophy
  • Classical Mythology
  • Classical Literature
  • Classical Reception
  • Classical Art and Architecture
  • Classical Oratory and Rhetoric
  • Greek and Roman Epigraphy
  • Greek and Roman Law
  • Greek and Roman Archaeology
  • Greek and Roman Papyrology
  • Late Antiquity
  • Religion in the Ancient World
  • Digital Humanities
  • Browse content in History
  • Colonialism and Imperialism
  • Diplomatic History
  • Environmental History
  • Genealogy, Heraldry, Names, and Honours
  • Genocide and Ethnic Cleansing
  • Historical Geography
  • History by Period
  • History of Agriculture
  • History of Education
  • History of Emotions
  • History of Gender and Sexuality
  • Industrial History
  • Intellectual History
  • International History
  • Labour History
  • Legal and Constitutional History
  • Local and Family History
  • Maritime History
  • Military History
  • National Liberation and Post-Colonialism
  • Oral History
  • Political History
  • Public History
  • Regional and National History
  • Revolutions and Rebellions
  • Slavery and Abolition of Slavery
  • Social and Cultural History
  • Theory, Methods, and Historiography
  • Urban History
  • World History
  • Browse content in Language Teaching and Learning
  • Language Learning (Specific Skills)
  • Language Teaching Theory and Methods
  • Browse content in Linguistics
  • Applied Linguistics
  • Cognitive Linguistics
  • Computational Linguistics
  • Forensic Linguistics
  • Grammar, Syntax and Morphology
  • Historical and Diachronic Linguistics
  • History of English
  • Language Acquisition
  • Language Variation
  • Language Families
  • Language Evolution
  • Language Reference
  • Lexicography
  • Linguistic Theories
  • Linguistic Typology
  • Linguistic Anthropology
  • Phonetics and Phonology
  • Psycholinguistics
  • Sociolinguistics
  • Translation and Interpretation
  • Writing Systems
  • Browse content in Literature
  • Bibliography
  • Children's Literature Studies
  • Literary Studies (Asian)
  • Literary Studies (European)
  • Literary Studies (Eco-criticism)
  • Literary Studies (Modernism)
  • Literary Studies (Romanticism)
  • Literary Studies (American)
  • Literary Studies - World
  • Literary Studies (1500 to 1800)
  • Literary Studies (19th Century)
  • Literary Studies (20th Century onwards)
  • Literary Studies (African American Literature)
  • Literary Studies (British and Irish)
  • Literary Studies (Early and Medieval)
  • Literary Studies (Fiction, Novelists, and Prose Writers)
  • Literary Studies (Gender Studies)
  • Literary Studies (Graphic Novels)
  • Literary Studies (History of the Book)
  • Literary Studies (Plays and Playwrights)
  • Literary Studies (Poetry and Poets)
  • Literary Studies (Postcolonial Literature)
  • Literary Studies (Queer Studies)
  • Literary Studies (Science Fiction)
  • Literary Studies (Travel Literature)
  • Literary Studies (War Literature)
  • Literary Studies (Women's Writing)
  • Literary Theory and Cultural Studies
  • Mythology and Folklore
  • Shakespeare Studies and Criticism
  • Browse content in Media Studies
  • Browse content in Music
  • Applied Music
  • Dance and Music
  • Ethics in Music
  • Ethnomusicology
  • Gender and Sexuality in Music
  • Medicine and Music
  • Music Cultures
  • Music and Religion
  • Music and Culture
  • Music and Media
  • Music Education and Pedagogy
  • Music Theory and Analysis
  • Musical Scores, Lyrics, and Libretti
  • Musical Structures, Styles, and Techniques
  • Musicology and Music History
  • Performance Practice and Studies
  • Race and Ethnicity in Music
  • Sound Studies
  • Browse content in Performing Arts
  • Browse content in Philosophy
  • Aesthetics and Philosophy of Art
  • Epistemology
  • Feminist Philosophy
  • History of Western Philosophy
  • Metaphysics
  • Moral Philosophy
  • Non-Western Philosophy
  • Philosophy of Science
  • Philosophy of Action
  • Philosophy of Law
  • Philosophy of Religion
  • Philosophy of Language
  • Philosophy of Mind
  • Philosophy of Perception
  • Philosophy of Mathematics and Logic
  • Practical Ethics
  • Social and Political Philosophy
  • Browse content in Religion
  • Biblical Studies
  • Christianity
  • East Asian Religions
  • History of Religion
  • Judaism and Jewish Studies
  • Qumran Studies
  • Religion and Education
  • Religion and Health
  • Religion and Politics
  • Religion and Science
  • Religion and Law
  • Religion and Art, Literature, and Music
  • Religious Studies
  • Browse content in Society and Culture
  • Cookery, Food, and Drink
  • Cultural Studies
  • Customs and Traditions
  • Ethical Issues and Debates
  • Hobbies, Games, Arts and Crafts
  • Natural world, Country Life, and Pets
  • Popular Beliefs and Controversial Knowledge
  • Sports and Outdoor Recreation
  • Technology and Society
  • Travel and Holiday
  • Visual Culture
  • Browse content in Law
  • Arbitration
  • Browse content in Company and Commercial Law
  • Commercial Law
  • Company Law
  • Browse content in Comparative Law
  • Systems of Law
  • Competition Law
  • Browse content in Constitutional and Administrative Law
  • Government Powers
  • Judicial Review
  • Local Government Law
  • Military and Defence Law
  • Parliamentary and Legislative Practice
  • Construction Law
  • Contract Law
  • Browse content in Criminal Law
  • Criminal Procedure
  • Criminal Evidence Law
  • Sentencing and Punishment
  • Employment and Labour Law
  • Environment and Energy Law
  • Browse content in Financial Law
  • Banking Law
  • Insolvency Law
  • History of Law
  • Human Rights and Immigration
  • Intellectual Property Law
  • Browse content in International Law
  • Private International Law and Conflict of Laws
  • Public International Law
  • IT and Communications Law
  • Jurisprudence and Philosophy of Law
  • Law and Politics
  • Law and Society
  • Browse content in Legal System and Practice
  • Courts and Procedure
  • Legal Skills and Practice
  • Primary Sources of Law
  • Regulation of Legal Profession
  • Medical and Healthcare Law
  • Browse content in Policing
  • Criminal Investigation and Detection
  • Police and Security Services
  • Police Procedure and Law
  • Police Regional Planning
  • Browse content in Property Law
  • Personal Property Law
  • Study and Revision
  • Terrorism and National Security Law
  • Browse content in Trusts Law
  • Wills and Probate or Succession
  • Browse content in Medicine and Health
  • Browse content in Allied Health Professions
  • Arts Therapies
  • Clinical Science
  • Dietetics and Nutrition
  • Occupational Therapy
  • Operating Department Practice
  • Physiotherapy
  • Radiography
  • Speech and Language Therapy
  • Browse content in Anaesthetics
  • General Anaesthesia
  • Neuroanaesthesia
  • Browse content in Clinical Medicine
  • Acute Medicine
  • Cardiovascular Medicine
  • Clinical Genetics
  • Clinical Pharmacology and Therapeutics
  • Dermatology
  • Endocrinology and Diabetes
  • Gastroenterology
  • Genito-urinary Medicine
  • Geriatric Medicine
  • Infectious Diseases
  • Medical Oncology
  • Medical Toxicology
  • Pain Medicine
  • Palliative Medicine
  • Rehabilitation Medicine
  • Respiratory Medicine and Pulmonology
  • Rheumatology
  • Sleep Medicine
  • Sports and Exercise Medicine
  • Clinical Neuroscience
  • Community Medical Services
  • Critical Care
  • Emergency Medicine
  • Forensic Medicine
  • Haematology
  • History of Medicine
  • Browse content in Medical Dentistry
  • Oral and Maxillofacial Surgery
  • Paediatric Dentistry
  • Restorative Dentistry and Orthodontics
  • Surgical Dentistry
  • Medical Ethics
  • Browse content in Medical Skills
  • Clinical Skills
  • Communication Skills
  • Nursing Skills
  • Surgical Skills
  • Medical Statistics and Methodology
  • Browse content in Neurology
  • Clinical Neurophysiology
  • Neuropathology
  • Nursing Studies
  • Browse content in Obstetrics and Gynaecology
  • Gynaecology
  • Occupational Medicine
  • Ophthalmology
  • Otolaryngology (ENT)
  • Browse content in Paediatrics
  • Neonatology
  • Browse content in Pathology
  • Chemical Pathology
  • Clinical Cytogenetics and Molecular Genetics
  • Histopathology
  • Medical Microbiology and Virology
  • Patient Education and Information
  • Browse content in Pharmacology
  • Psychopharmacology
  • Browse content in Popular Health
  • Caring for Others
  • Complementary and Alternative Medicine
  • Self-help and Personal Development
  • Browse content in Preclinical Medicine
  • Cell Biology
  • Molecular Biology and Genetics
  • Reproduction, Growth and Development
  • Primary Care
  • Professional Development in Medicine
  • Browse content in Psychiatry
  • Addiction Medicine
  • Child and Adolescent Psychiatry
  • Forensic Psychiatry
  • Learning Disabilities
  • Old Age Psychiatry
  • Psychotherapy
  • Browse content in Public Health and Epidemiology
  • Epidemiology
  • Public Health
  • Browse content in Radiology
  • Clinical Radiology
  • Interventional Radiology
  • Nuclear Medicine
  • Radiation Oncology
  • Reproductive Medicine
  • Browse content in Surgery
  • Cardiothoracic Surgery
  • Gastro-intestinal and Colorectal Surgery
  • General Surgery
  • Neurosurgery
  • Paediatric Surgery
  • Peri-operative Care
  • Plastic and Reconstructive Surgery
  • Surgical Oncology
  • Transplant Surgery
  • Trauma and Orthopaedic Surgery
  • Vascular Surgery
  • Browse content in Science and Mathematics
  • Browse content in Biological Sciences
  • Aquatic Biology
  • Biochemistry
  • Bioinformatics and Computational Biology
  • Developmental Biology
  • Ecology and Conservation
  • Evolutionary Biology
  • Genetics and Genomics
  • Microbiology
  • Molecular and Cell Biology
  • Natural History
  • Plant Sciences and Forestry
  • Research Methods in Life Sciences
  • Structural Biology
  • Systems Biology
  • Zoology and Animal Sciences
  • Browse content in Chemistry
  • Analytical Chemistry
  • Computational Chemistry
  • Crystallography
  • Environmental Chemistry
  • Industrial Chemistry
  • Inorganic Chemistry
  • Materials Chemistry
  • Medicinal Chemistry
  • Mineralogy and Gems
  • Organic Chemistry
  • Physical Chemistry
  • Polymer Chemistry
  • Study and Communication Skills in Chemistry
  • Theoretical Chemistry
  • Browse content in Computer Science
  • Artificial Intelligence
  • Computer Architecture and Logic Design
  • Game Studies
  • Human-Computer Interaction
  • Mathematical Theory of Computation
  • Programming Languages
  • Software Engineering
  • Systems Analysis and Design
  • Virtual Reality
  • Browse content in Computing
  • Business Applications
  • Computer Security
  • Computer Games
  • Computer Networking and Communications
  • Digital Lifestyle
  • Graphical and Digital Media Applications
  • Operating Systems
  • Browse content in Earth Sciences and Geography
  • Atmospheric Sciences
  • Environmental Geography
  • Geology and the Lithosphere
  • Maps and Map-making
  • Meteorology and Climatology
  • Oceanography and Hydrology
  • Palaeontology
  • Physical Geography and Topography
  • Regional Geography
  • Soil Science
  • Urban Geography
  • Browse content in Engineering and Technology
  • Agriculture and Farming
  • Biological Engineering
  • Civil Engineering, Surveying, and Building
  • Electronics and Communications Engineering
  • Energy Technology
  • Engineering (General)
  • Environmental Science, Engineering, and Technology
  • History of Engineering and Technology
  • Mechanical Engineering and Materials
  • Technology of Industrial Chemistry
  • Transport Technology and Trades
  • Browse content in Environmental Science
  • Applied Ecology (Environmental Science)
  • Conservation of the Environment (Environmental Science)
  • Environmental Sustainability
  • Environmentalist Thought and Ideology (Environmental Science)
  • Management of Land and Natural Resources (Environmental Science)
  • Natural Disasters (Environmental Science)
  • Nuclear Issues (Environmental Science)
  • Pollution and Threats to the Environment (Environmental Science)
  • Social Impact of Environmental Issues (Environmental Science)
  • History of Science and Technology
  • Browse content in Materials Science
  • Ceramics and Glasses
  • Composite Materials
  • Metals, Alloying, and Corrosion
  • Nanotechnology
  • Browse content in Mathematics
  • Applied Mathematics
  • Biomathematics and Statistics
  • History of Mathematics
  • Mathematical Education
  • Mathematical Finance
  • Mathematical Analysis
  • Numerical and Computational Mathematics
  • Probability and Statistics
  • Pure Mathematics
  • Browse content in Neuroscience
  • Cognition and Behavioural Neuroscience
  • Development of the Nervous System
  • Disorders of the Nervous System
  • History of Neuroscience
  • Invertebrate Neurobiology
  • Molecular and Cellular Systems
  • Neuroendocrinology and Autonomic Nervous System
  • Neuroscientific Techniques
  • Sensory and Motor Systems
  • Browse content in Physics
  • Astronomy and Astrophysics
  • Atomic, Molecular, and Optical Physics
  • Biological and Medical Physics
  • Classical Mechanics
  • Computational Physics
  • Condensed Matter Physics
  • Electromagnetism, Optics, and Acoustics
  • History of Physics
  • Mathematical and Statistical Physics
  • Measurement Science
  • Nuclear Physics
  • Particles and Fields
  • Plasma Physics
  • Quantum Physics
  • Relativity and Gravitation
  • Semiconductor and Mesoscopic Physics
  • Browse content in Psychology
  • Affective Sciences
  • Clinical Psychology
  • Cognitive Neuroscience
  • Cognitive Psychology
  • Criminal and Forensic Psychology
  • Developmental Psychology
  • Educational Psychology
  • Evolutionary Psychology
  • Health Psychology
  • History and Systems in Psychology
  • Music Psychology
  • Neuropsychology
  • Organizational Psychology
  • Psychological Assessment and Testing
  • Psychology of Human-Technology Interaction
  • Psychology Professional Development and Training
  • Research Methods in Psychology
  • Social Psychology
  • Browse content in Social Sciences
  • Browse content in Anthropology
  • Anthropology of Religion
  • Human Evolution
  • Medical Anthropology
  • Physical Anthropology
  • Regional Anthropology
  • Social and Cultural Anthropology
  • Theory and Practice of Anthropology
  • Browse content in Business and Management
  • Business Strategy
  • Business History
  • Business Ethics
  • Business and Government
  • Business and Technology
  • Business and the Environment
  • Comparative Management
  • Corporate Governance
  • Corporate Social Responsibility
  • Entrepreneurship
  • Health Management
  • Human Resource Management
  • Industrial and Employment Relations
  • Industry Studies
  • Information and Communication Technologies
  • International Business
  • Knowledge Management
  • Management and Management Techniques
  • Operations Management
  • Organizational Theory and Behaviour
  • Pensions and Pension Management
  • Public and Nonprofit Management
  • Strategic Management
  • Supply Chain Management
  • Browse content in Criminology and Criminal Justice
  • Criminal Justice
  • Criminology
  • Forms of Crime
  • International and Comparative Criminology
  • Youth Violence and Juvenile Justice
  • Development Studies
  • Browse content in Economics
  • Agricultural, Environmental, and Natural Resource Economics
  • Asian Economics
  • Behavioural Finance
  • Behavioural Economics and Neuroeconomics
  • Econometrics and Mathematical Economics
  • Economic Systems
  • Economic Methodology
  • Economic History
  • Economic Development and Growth
  • Financial Markets
  • Financial Institutions and Services
  • General Economics and Teaching
  • Health, Education, and Welfare
  • History of Economic Thought
  • International Economics
  • Labour and Demographic Economics
  • Law and Economics
  • Macroeconomics and Monetary Economics
  • Microeconomics
  • Public Economics
  • Urban, Rural, and Regional Economics
  • Welfare Economics
  • Browse content in Education
  • Adult Education and Continuous Learning
  • Care and Counselling of Students
  • Early Childhood and Elementary Education
  • Educational Equipment and Technology
  • Educational Strategies and Policy
  • Higher and Further Education
  • Organization and Management of Education
  • Philosophy and Theory of Education
  • Schools Studies
  • Secondary Education
  • Teaching of a Specific Subject
  • Teaching of Specific Groups and Special Educational Needs
  • Teaching Skills and Techniques
  • Browse content in Environment
  • Applied Ecology (Social Science)
  • Climate Change
  • Conservation of the Environment (Social Science)
  • Environmentalist Thought and Ideology (Social Science)
  • Natural Disasters (Environment)
  • Social Impact of Environmental Issues (Social Science)
  • Browse content in Human Geography
  • Cultural Geography
  • Economic Geography
  • Political Geography
  • Browse content in Interdisciplinary Studies
  • Communication Studies
  • Museums, Libraries, and Information Sciences
  • Browse content in Politics
  • African Politics
  • Asian Politics
  • Chinese Politics
  • Comparative Politics
  • Conflict Politics
  • Elections and Electoral Studies
  • Environmental Politics
  • Ethnic Politics
  • European Union
  • Foreign Policy
  • Gender and Politics
  • Human Rights and Politics
  • Indian Politics
  • International Relations
  • International Organization (Politics)
  • International Political Economy
  • Irish Politics
  • Latin American Politics
  • Middle Eastern Politics
  • Political Methodology
  • Political Communication
  • Political Philosophy
  • Political Sociology
  • Political Theory
  • Political Behaviour
  • Political Economy
  • Political Institutions
  • Politics and Law
  • Politics of Development
  • Public Administration
  • Public Policy
  • Quantitative Political Methodology
  • Regional Political Studies
  • Russian Politics
  • Security Studies
  • State and Local Government
  • UK Politics
  • US Politics
  • Browse content in Regional and Area Studies
  • African Studies
  • Asian Studies
  • East Asian Studies
  • Japanese Studies
  • Latin American Studies
  • Middle Eastern Studies
  • Native American Studies
  • Scottish Studies
  • Browse content in Research and Information
  • Research Methods
  • Browse content in Social Work
  • Addictions and Substance Misuse
  • Adoption and Fostering
  • Care of the Elderly
  • Child and Adolescent Social Work
  • Couple and Family Social Work
  • Direct Practice and Clinical Social Work
  • Emergency Services
  • Human Behaviour and the Social Environment
  • International and Global Issues in Social Work
  • Mental and Behavioural Health
  • Social Justice and Human Rights
  • Social Policy and Advocacy
  • Social Work and Crime and Justice
  • Social Work Macro Practice
  • Social Work Practice Settings
  • Social Work Research and Evidence-based Practice
  • Welfare and Benefit Systems
  • Browse content in Sociology
  • Childhood Studies
  • Community Development
  • Comparative and Historical Sociology
  • Economic Sociology
  • Gender and Sexuality
  • Gerontology and Ageing
  • Health, Illness, and Medicine
  • Marriage and the Family
  • Migration Studies
  • Occupations, Professions, and Work
  • Organizations
  • Population and Demography
  • Race and Ethnicity
  • Social Theory
  • Social Movements and Social Change
  • Social Research and Statistics
  • Social Stratification, Inequality, and Mobility
  • Sociology of Religion
  • Sociology of Education
  • Sport and Leisure
  • Urban and Rural Studies
  • Browse content in Warfare and Defence
  • Defence Strategy, Planning, and Research
  • Land Forces and Warfare
  • Military Administration
  • Military Life and Institutions
  • Naval Forces and Warfare
  • Other Warfare and Defence Issues
  • Peace Studies and Conflict Resolution
  • Weapons and Equipment

Deadly Vices

  • < Previous
  • Next chapter >

1 Introduction: Vices and Virtue‐Theory

  • Published: June 2006
  • Cite Icon Cite
  • Permissions Icon Permissions

This introductory chapter begins with a discussion of the vices considered in this essay, namely, sloth, envy, avarice, pride, anger, lust, and gluttony. It argues that these so-called ‘deadly sins’ were correctly named and correctly classed together. Irrespective of their theological background, they are similar in structure in that the agent’s thoughts and desires, while differing in content depending on the vice in question, focus primarily on the self and its position in the world. They are similar also in that in each case they are destructive of that self and prevent its flourishing.

Personal account

  • Sign in with email/username & password
  • Get email alerts
  • Save searches
  • Purchase content
  • Activate your purchase/trial code
  • Add your ORCID iD

Institutional access

Sign in with a library card.

  • Sign in with username/password
  • Recommend to your librarian
  • Institutional account management
  • Get help with access

Access to content on Oxford Academic is often provided through institutional subscriptions and purchases. If you are a member of an institution with an active account, you may be able to access content in one of the following ways:

IP based access

Typically, access is provided across an institutional network to a range of IP addresses. This authentication occurs automatically, and it is not possible to sign out of an IP authenticated account.

Choose this option to get remote access when outside your institution. Shibboleth/Open Athens technology is used to provide single sign-on between your institution’s website and Oxford Academic.

  • Click Sign in through your institution.
  • Select your institution from the list provided, which will take you to your institution's website to sign in.
  • When on the institution site, please use the credentials provided by your institution. Do not use an Oxford Academic personal account.
  • Following successful sign in, you will be returned to Oxford Academic.

If your institution is not listed or you cannot sign in to your institution’s website, please contact your librarian or administrator.

Enter your library card number to sign in. If you cannot sign in, please contact your librarian.

Society Members

Society member access to a journal is achieved in one of the following ways:

Sign in through society site

Many societies offer single sign-on between the society website and Oxford Academic. If you see ‘Sign in through society site’ in the sign in pane within a journal:

  • Click Sign in through society site.
  • When on the society site, please use the credentials provided by that society. Do not use an Oxford Academic personal account.

If you do not have a society account or have forgotten your username or password, please contact your society.

Sign in using a personal account

Some societies use Oxford Academic personal accounts to provide access to their members. See below.

A personal account can be used to get email alerts, save searches, purchase content, and activate subscriptions.

Some societies use Oxford Academic personal accounts to provide access to their members.

Viewing your signed in accounts

Click the account icon in the top right to:

  • View your signed in personal account and access account management features.
  • View the institutional accounts that are providing access.

Signed in but can't access content

Oxford Academic is home to a wide variety of products. The institutional subscription may not cover the content that you are trying to access. If you believe you should have access to that content, please contact your librarian.

For librarians and administrators, your personal account also provides access to institutional account management. Here you will find options to view and activate subscriptions, manage institutional settings and access options, access usage statistics, and more.

Our books are available by subscription or purchase to libraries and institutions.

Month: Total Views:
October 2022 24
November 2022 22
December 2022 7
January 2023 8
February 2023 2
March 2023 7
May 2023 2
June 2023 1
July 2023 4
August 2023 3
September 2023 4
October 2023 42
November 2023 20
December 2023 18
January 2024 7
February 2024 1
March 2024 13
April 2024 136
May 2024 12
June 2024 9
  • About Oxford Academic
  • Publish journals with us
  • University press partners
  • What we publish
  • New features  
  • Open access
  • Rights and permissions
  • Accessibility
  • Advertising
  • Media enquiries
  • Oxford University Press
  • Oxford Languages
  • University of Oxford

Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the University's objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide

  • Copyright © 2024 Oxford University Press
  • Cookie settings
  • Cookie policy
  • Privacy policy
  • Legal notice

This Feature Is Available To Subscribers Only

Sign In or Create an Account

This PDF is available to Subscribers Only

For full access to this pdf, sign in to an existing account, or purchase an annual subscription.

  • Free Samples
  • Premium Essays
  • Editing Services Editing Proofreading Rewriting
  • Extra Tools Essay Topic Generator Thesis Generator Citation Generator GPA Calculator Study Guides Donate Paper
  • Essay Writing Help
  • About Us About Us Testimonials FAQ

Essays on vices

  • Studentshare
  • TERMS & CONDITIONS
  • PRIVACY POLICY
  • COOKIES POLICY

PhilNews

  • #WalangPasok
  • Breaking News
  • Photography
  • ALS Exam Results
  • Aeronautical Engineering Board Exam Result
  • Agricultural and Biosystem Engineering Board Exam Result
  • Agriculturist Board Exam Result
  • Architecture Exam Results
  • BAR Exam Results
  • CPA Exam Results
  • Certified Plant Mechanic Exam Result
  • Chemical Engineering Exam Results
  • Chemical Technician Exam Result
  • Chemist Licensure Exam Result
  • Civil Engineering Exam Results
  • Civil Service Exam Results
  • Criminology Exam Results
  • Customs Broker Exam Result
  • Dental Hygienist Board Exam Result
  • Dental Technologist Board Exam Result
  • Dentist Licensure Exam Result
  • ECE Exam Results
  • ECT Board Exam Result
  • Environmental Planner Exam Result
  • Featured Exam Results
  • Fisheries Professional Exam Result
  • Geodetic Engineering Board Exam Result
  • Guidance Counselor Board Exam Result
  • Interior Design Board Exam Result
  • LET Exam Results
  • Landscape Architect Board Exam Result
  • Librarian Exam Result
  • Master Plumber Exam Result
  • Mechanical Engineering Exam Results
  • MedTech Exam Results
  • Metallurgical Engineering Board Exam Result
  • Midwives Board Exam Result
  • Mining Engineering Board Exam Result
  • NAPOLCOM Exam Results
  • Naval Architect and Marine Engineer Board Exam Result
  • Nursing Exam Results
  • Nutritionist Dietitian Board Exam Result
  • Occupational Therapist Board Exam Result
  • Ocular Pharmacologist Exam Result
  • Optometrist Board Exam Result
  • Pharmacist Licensure Exam Result
  • Physical Therapist Board Exam
  • Physician Exam Results
  • Principal Exam Results
  • Professional Forester Exam Result
  • Psychologist Board Exam Result
  • Psychometrician Board Exam Result
  • REE Board Exam Result
  • RME Board Exam Result
  • Radiologic Technology Board Exam Result
  • Real Estate Appraiser Exam Result
  • Real Estate Broker Exam Result
  • Real Estate Consultant Exam Result
  • Respiratory Therapist Board Exam Result 
  • Sanitary Engineering Board Exam Result 
  • Social Worker Exam Result
  • UPCAT Exam Results
  • Upcoming Exam Result
  • Veterinarian Licensure Exam Result 
  • X-Ray Technologist Exam Result
  • Programming
  • Smartphones
  • Web Hosting
  • Social Media
  • SWERTRES RESULT
  • EZ2 RESULT TODAY
  • STL RESULT TODAY
  • 6/58 LOTTO RESULT
  • 6/55 LOTTO RESULT
  • 6/49 LOTTO RESULT
  • 6/45 LOTTO RESULT
  • 6/42 LOTTO RESULT
  • 6-Digit Lotto Result
  • 4-Digit Lotto Result
  • 3D RESULT TODAY
  • 2D Lotto Result
  • English to Tagalog
  • English-Tagalog Translate
  • Maikling Kwento
  • EUR to PHP Today
  • Pounds to Peso
  • Binibining Pilipinas
  • Miss Universe
  • Family (Pamilya)
  • Life (Buhay)
  • Love (Pag-ibig)
  • School (Eskwela)
  • Work (Trabaho)
  • Pinoy Jokes
  • Tagalog Jokes
  • Referral Letters
  • Student Letters
  • Employee Letters
  • Business Letters
  • Pag-IBIG Fund
  • Home Credit Cash Loan
  • Pick Up Lines Tagalog
  • Pork Dishes
  • Lotto Result Today
  • Viral Videos

Essay About Vices? – Short Descriptive Essay Example

Example of short descriptive essay regarding vices.

WHAT ARE VICES? – In this article, we are going to give an example of an essay regarding the effects of vices, especially to the youth.

Descriptive essays use a detailed way of writing that often gives a fuller visualization for the reader. Here is an example of one regarding the effects of vices:

Vices are habits of moral depravity or corruption. Young adults are prone to these kinds of doings. It is infrequent to find a place that is free from social vices. This portrays that these vices are common in all educational institutions causing problems and distractions to millennials.

Essay About Vices? – Short Descriptive Essay Example

This generally troubled today’s generation in terms of their characters, conduct and response to daily activities which is not beneficial to an individual. The related studies states that teenagers tend to be prone in habits of drinking alcohol and smoking.

Students in social surroundings frequently pair smoking and drinking together. Also, gambling is another corrupted habit and it states that adolescence practice this occasionally.

Lastly, computer addiction is shown to be another cause even though it is popular among male students. To sum everything up, alcoholism, smoking, gambling, drugs, and computer addiction are the most common vices among young adults.

Thanks for reading. We aim to provide our readers with the freshest and most in-demand content. Come back next time for the latest news here on Philnews.

Like this article? READ ALSO: Who Is Your Digital Self? – Simple Essay Example

Leave a Comment Cancel reply

IMAGES

  1. 421054702-Baby-Thesis-The-Effects-of-Vices-on-Academic-Peformance-of

    thesis about vices

  2. Jose Medina, The Epistemology of Resistance, ch. 1 Vices and Virtues

    thesis about vices

  3. Intellectual Vices: The Truth About Human Nature and its Impact

    thesis about vices

  4. 💐 Vices essay. Vices. 2022-10-10

    thesis about vices

  5. (PDF) Virtues and Vices of reasonableness. What does Common sense Tell

    thesis about vices

  6. (PDF) Epistemic Vices and Vice Epistemology

    thesis about vices

VIDEO

  1. THESIS PRINTED ON A DIGITAL FOIL PRINTER

COMMENTS

  1. The Impact of Vices on Student Motivation and Academic Performance

    Conclusion. In conclusion, the prevalence of vices among the younger generation, particularly college students, raises concerns about their impact on motivation and academic performance. Alcoholism, smoking, computer games, and gambling emerge as the most common vices, each presenting unique challenges. Understanding the underlying factors ...

  2. Students Vices and their Academic Performance

    How students vices such as procrastination and absenteeism affect their academic performance. The present study explored whether a significant relationship exists between academic procrastination and academic achievement in high school learners within South Africa. It furthermore examined whether certain personality traits of individuals are ...

  3. INFLUENCE OF SOCIAL VICES ON STUDENTS' ACADEMIC ...

    vices prevalent in Nigerian secondary schools as evident in series of research work as they affect the accomplishment of the objectives of secondary education. Causes and effects of social vices on the academic performance of secondary schools students in Nigeria were also discussed. A model explaining the interaction of social vices on the

  4. PDF The Social Transformation of Vice

    Vice implies moral ambivalence, that is conduct that a person may enjoy and deplore at the same time. As a corollary, moral ambivalence generates. controversy over public policy concerning certain activities. If an activity is clearly accepted as immoral, as are robbery and burglary, no difficult public.

  5. Vices, Virtues, and Consequences: Essays in Moral and Political ...

    Modern moral philosophy has long been dominated by two basic theories, Kantianism or deontology, on the one hand, and utilitarianism or consequentialism, on the other. Increasing dissatisfaction with these theories and their variants has led in recent years to the emergence of a different theory, the theory of virtue ethics.¹ According to ...

  6. Students' Engagement in Social Vices and Social Studies Students

    The results of the Statistical analysis revealed that social vices such as deadly diseases, dangerous acts like engagement in illegal act such as cultism, act of smoking and taking of illegal ...

  7. Virtues and Vices : and other essays in moral philosophy

    'Foot stands out among contemporary ethical theorists because of her conviction that virtues and vices are more central ethical notions than rights, duties, justice, or consequences - the primary focus of most other contemporary theorists. This volume brings together a dozen essays published between 1957 and 1977, and includes two new ones as well.

  8. PDF Engagement in Social Vices and Social Studies Students Academic

    this depicts that these vices are present in all edu cational centers be it primary, secondary and tertiary institutions (Dishion, Andrew, Spracklen and Patternso n, 2010). Vice is a latin word ³vitium ´ meaning defect or failing. Elsewhere, Smithson Amato and Pearle ( 201 1) see vice as a bad habit or immoral activities. Vice

  9. (PDF) Social Vices

    Atoyin Cassidy. This study investigated the influence of social vices on the information and communication management in Tertiary institutions. To achieve this objective, four questions were raised. A sample of 50 students each was selected from four tertiary institutions in Ibadan metropolis, totaling 200, using the technique of random sampling.

  10. Asking questions about vices really does increase vice behavior

    Finally we will address the issue of whether one should continue to have faith in the conclusion we drew in Williams et al. ( 2006 ), that simply asking a question about a vice behavior can actually lead to increases in the respondents' engaging in the behavior. In the original experiment there was also a condition in which participants ...

  11. Virtues and Their Vices

    Taken together these essays provide a lucid and inviting overview of the epistemic virtues and the ways that virtue epistemology enriches our thinking about epistemic assessments, strategies, and goals. Given the larger theme of the collection (virtues and their vices), however, I was left wanting a substantive discussion of various epistemic ...

  12. The Privation Theory of the Vices

    Virtues and vices are very widely and naturally regarded as what Aristotle called hexeis - i.e., roughly, as character traits. ... After a survey of the debate to date, this article argues that the thesis of situationism is ill-supported by the available evidence. Situationists overlook the explanatory potential of a large class of global ...

  13. A Critique of Students' Vices and the Effect on Quality of Graduates of

    Each of these vices and the possible social and academic implications are explained. Major employers of Nigerian graduates have widely agreed on quality decline in higher education in the country, particularly in the areas of communication in oral and written English and technical proficiency. It is recommended that the responsibility of ...

  14. Baby Thesis The Effects of Vices On Academic Peformance of ...

    Baby Thesis The Effects of Vices on Academic Peformance of Students - Free download as Word Doc (.doc / .docx), PDF File (.pdf), Text File (.txt) or read online for free. The document discusses the negative impacts of vices such as alcohol, smoking, gambling, and excessive social media/video game use on students. It notes that these vices have become more common among youth as influences like ...

  15. Engagement In Vices and Self Esteem of Senior High School ...

    The percentage of females aged 16- who do vices also rose from 20% to 21%. Twenty% of males smoke, compared with 17% of females. Men between 25-34 years of age have given up on the biggest number of vices, with 26% doing vices in 2014, down from 30% in 2013. Of males 16-24 years of age, the percentage has fallen from 26% to 25%.

  16. A novel understanding of the nature of epistemic vice

    Vice epistemology is the study of the "nature, identity and epistemological significance of intellectual vices" (Cassam, 2016, p. 159). It involves identifying and analyzing certain character traits, attitudes and/or modes of thinking that can account for imperfect epistemic states (e.g., false beliefs, deficiency of epistemic goods, etc.).

  17. Introduction: Vices and Virtue‐Theory

    T he vices to be discussed in this essay are those which in Christian theology were most commonly selected as bringing death to the soul, namely sloth, envy, avarice, pride, anger, lust, and gluttony. My contention is that these so‐called 'deadly sins' were correctly so named, and correctly classed together. Irrespective of their theological background they can be seen to be similar in ...

  18. Essay On Virtues And Vices

    A virtue is something that can be praised upon however it is also make us good and obedient to the law. Virtue makes us good and obedient to the laws that are forced upon us. There are two types of virtues one is a moral virtue which comes from habits while intellectual virtue comes from knowledge.

  19. VICES: CAUSES AND EFFECTS AMONG HIGH SCHOOL STUDENTS

    CONCLUSION: VICES: CAUSES AND EFFECTS AMONG HIGH SCHOOL STUDENTS THESIS STATEMENT: Vices are considered not good for High School Students for it causes public problems and may result a shortcoming to one's self. According to a survey conducted by the social Weather Station in the

  20. Vices and Its Effects To The Students

    Vices and its effects to the students - Free download as Powerpoint Presentation (.ppt / .pptx), PDF File (.pdf), Text File (.txt) or view presentation slides online. The document discusses a study on the vices and their effects on Grade 11 students. It aims to identify the students' vices, reasons for having them, and their impacts. The researchers surveyed 8 students and found that their ...

  21. Essays on Vices. Free essay topics and examples about Vices

    1 pages (308 words) , Download 6. Free. The essay " Vices and Passions" presents ambition, seduction, excess, wastefulness, and fear to be the top Vices I am vulnerable to. Since Descartes considers the aforementioned conditions as Vices, I understand that he implies that these things are good and essential to life....

  22. Vices: Causes and Effects among High School Students

    THESIS STATEMENT: Vices are considered not good for High School Students for it causes public problems and may result a shortcoming to one's self. According to a survey conducted by the social Weather Station in the year 2012, 56% of Filipino teenagers are into different vices. EFFECTS OF PRACTICING.

  23. Essay About Vices?

    Descriptive essays use a detailed way of writing that often gives a fuller visualization for the reader. Here is an example of one regarding the effects of vices: Vices are habits of moral depravity or corruption. Young adults are prone to these kinds of doings. It is infrequent to find a place that is free from social vices.