• Search Menu
  • Sign in through your institution
  • Advance articles
  • Editor's Choice
  • Special Collections
  • Author Guidelines
  • Submission Site
  • Open Access
  • Reasons to submit
  • About BioScience
  • Journals Career Network
  • Editorial Board
  • Advertising and Corporate Services
  • Self-Archiving Policy
  • Potentially Offensive Content
  • Terms and Conditions
  • Journals on Oxford Academic
  • Books on Oxford Academic

Issue Cover

Article Contents

References cited.

  • < Previous

Ethics for Wildlife Conservation: Overcoming the Human–Nature Dualism

Barbara Paterson (e-mail [email protected] ) is with the Avian Demography Unit, Department of Statistical Sciences, University of Cape Town, Rondebosch 7701, South Africa

  • Article contents
  • Figures & tables
  • Supplementary Data

Barbara Paterson, Ethics for Wildlife Conservation: Overcoming the Human–Nature Dualism, BioScience , Volume 56, Issue 2, February 2006, Pages 144–150, https://doi.org/10.1641/0006-3568(2006)056[0144:EFWCOT]2.0.CO;2

  • Permissions Icon Permissions

This article contrasts the instrumental-value approach, extensionist approach, and biocentric approach to environmental ethics with the Buddhist approach of Daisaku Ikeda in terms of their meaning for wildlife conservation. I argue that both anthropocentric and biocentric approaches create a false dichotomy between humans and nature and are not helpful to modern wildlife conservation, which aims to balance the needs of people with the conservation of nature. The views of Daisaku Ikeda, in particular the principle of dependent origination and the theory of the oneness of life and its environment, constitute one alternative approach that does not separate humans from the natural world but places people within the web of all living things.

Although there is disagreement regarding the proper human relationship toward the rest of the natural world, most conservationists agree that biological diversity is valuable and that the extinction of species should be avoided where possible ( Cafaro and Primack 2001 ). Justifications for these principles vary, ranging from arguments that emphasize the instrumental value of other species for humans to ethical theories that assert that wild species have intrinsic value.

In the face of increasing human population and the related pressures on nonhuman species and their habitats, conservation efforts have to reconcile the conservation of nature with the needs of people. Especially in developing countries, people's livelihoods depend on the extraction of natural resources. It is therefore not surprising that arguments for the conservation of wildlife stress the instrumental value that certain species have for people, a value that can often be translated into economic terms. Such reasoning does not necessarily support the reckless exploitation of the environment. Rather, these arguments support the idea that species should be carefully managed as natural resources for human benefit. In fact, most international environmental policymaking is underpinned by a broadly anthropocentric approach to environmental value. At the level of popular political debate, the ethical agenda is largely composed of resource management concerns ( Palmer 2003 ). The most commonly cited definition of sustainable development as “development that meets the needs of the present without compromising the ability of future generations to meet their own needs” ( WCED 1987 ) is anthropocentric ( Cafaro and Primack 2001 ). Accordingly, it can be argued that species deserve to be protected and conserved insofar as they are good for people. The preamble to the Convention on Biodiversity, however, affirms the intrinsic value of biological diversity even before listing other values such as ecological, genetic, and economic value ( SCBD 2003 ).

The question of whether intrinsic value can indeed be found in anything but human beings is controversial. The debate on environmental ethics is thus largely concerned with finding out whether intrinsic value in nonhumans is possible or even necessary in order to develop universal theories why humans should protect their natural environment. This theoretical debate on whether nonhumans have value independent of humans is criticized by environmental pragmatists, who claim that while philosophers argue, the environment burns.

In this article I contrast four categories of approaches toward environmental ethics—the instrumental-value approach, the extensionist approach, the biocentric approach, and the Buddhist approach of Daisaku Ikeda—and identify the meaning of each of these approaches for wildlife conservation. I argue that both anthropocentric and biocentric approaches to environmental ethics create a false dichotomy between humans and nature and are thus not useful as an underpinning for modern wildlife conservation policies, which aim to balance the needs of people with the conservation of nature. The views of Daisaku Ikeda, particularly the principle of dependent origination and the theory of the oneness of life and its environment, are one alternative approach that does not separate humans from the natural world but places people within the web of all living things.

Instrumental value in wildlife: What species are good for

There are several frequently employed arguments for the conservation of wild species. These arguments have in common that they focus on the value species have for humans. Arguments that stress the instrumental value of species for human well-being are called anthropocentric. In this view, wild species are only good inasmuch as they are good for something, that is, have a use or a value for humans. Such a value may be economic ( Myers 1983 ). Some wildlife species are of high economic value for tourism, hunting, and live sale ( Child 1970 ). The value of an animal in a live sale or the value of a hunting trophy can be expressed in direct cash terms. Indirect economic values accrue from the roles species play in recreation and ecotourism, waste disposal, climate regulation, and protection of soil and water resources.

Species also have aesthetic value in that they contribute to the diversity and beauty of the planet ( Myers 1979a ). The safari and ecotourism industries attest to the aesthetic value people attach to particular wildlife species, which causes tourists to travel large distances and to pay large amounts of money for game-viewing safaris. At least for developed nations, where opportunities to observe wildlife are steadily decreasing, it can be said that the quality of life will decline substantially with the loss of species diversity. In many developing countries, game viewing and trophy hunting generate considerable sums of money, and the aesthetic value of wildlife can thus be directly linked to an economic value.

An interesting question arises here, namely, to what degree and in what way do tribal communities see wildlife as valuable for quality of life? Members of developed nations translate the wildlife experience into a monetary value for local communities. But what value do the local communities attach to wildlife? Newmark and colleagues (1993) have shown that the support for or opposition to protected areas in Tanzania by neighboring community members is based on economic values, as had previously been found in Rwanda and Brazil. Kangwana and Mako (2001) , on the other hand, state that later surveys indicate “that people living around the [Tarangire National] Park hold cultural values which drive their desire to see that wildlife continues to exist in their surroundings” and that “wildlife is seen [by local people] as having a value beyond its simple economic costs and benefits.” In Namibia, traditional tribal authorities support the establishment of protected areas to help wildlife return to their homelands (Mauney 2004).

Nature and wildlife are also a great philosophical and spiritual resource, serving as inspiration for religious, philosophical, and spiritual thought and experience. This is not only true for the direct experience of wildlife; the mere idea that we share the Earth with blue whales, orangutans, and cheetahs, for example, can be inspiring. What is valued here is the simple possibility that a species exists and survives, although one might never see it ( Fisher 2001 ).

Many species, including endangered ones, are expected to have agricultural, industrial, and medical benefits. To lose such species diminishes the genetic stock of wild animals, so it is prudent to save them. We might not know now which species will turn out to be useful in the future; therefore, protection should extend from the current obviously useful species to those that are currently considered less useful. Myers (1979b) urges us to “conserve our global stock,” to conserve species in order to protect useful genetic material. The purpose of protecting species is thus for their “enlightened exploitation” ( Rolston 2001 ).

It is frequently argued that many species that are not necessarily directly useful to humans still play important roles in the ecosystem. Although the loss of a few species might not be too serious now, the loss of many species will threaten the processes and interdependencies of the ecosystem on which we as humans depend, in ways that cannot possibly be foreseen. Thus species are part of a life-support system: Earth is seen as a biological habitat or home. Every species contributes to the planet's biodiversity, which keeps ecosystems healthy ( Ehrlich and Ehrlich 1982 ).

Species also serve as indicators of ecosystem health. We need to study species and their roles within ecosystems to understand their interdependencies and to predict the impacts of our actions on the environment. Species offer clues to understanding natural history and thus have historical value as records of past processes. This argument views species as a biological Rosetta stone that may enable the deciphering of the hieroglyphs of natural history ( Rolston 2001 ). According to this argument, species have scientific value because they provide humans with insights into the text of natural history, which humans need in order to understand their own environment. Some species are curiosities and a source of fascination to enthusiastic naturalists. Generally speaking, wildlife species can be a basis for creative and intellectual thought. One of the outcomes of such thought is a better-informed perspective on the natural history of the planet and its life-forms.

Arguments centering on the instrumental value of wildlife provide a basis for valuing and protecting species. Nonetheless, arguments for the conservation of species that are based on instrumental value are problematic for conservation workers, because they put the onus of proof on the side of the conservator. Conservationists have to explicitly and successfully show that a species is worth protecting because of its value to humans; otherwise, it may well be assumed that that there is no such value. Thus this line of argument, if used alone, presents ongoing challenges for endangered species conservation, since many rare and endangered species have little instrumental value. Moreover, arguments based on instrumental value can also provide grounds for extinguishing species (e.g., pests) or for saving one species rather than another (e.g., when resources are constrained).

Forced to prove the value of wild species, many conservationists favor the economic argument, because economic value can be measured in objective terms. The economic returns to be gained from species conservation can be expressed in monetary terms, thus providing powerful arguments. In comparison, the scientific argument, the ecosystem argument, and the aesthetic argument are considered “unlikely to stand up against man-made pressures to modify and disrupt natural environments” ( Myers 1979a ). Consequently, it is argued that wildlife must pay its way, and economic benefits must be stressed to ensure that wildlife will survive in the face of other profitable forms of land use. This view takes for granted the manmade pressures for environmental change. Although the instrumental-value approach is based on the need to conserve species as resources for the benefit of people, this view is underpinned by a negative concept of humanity. Humans are seen as driven first and foremost by self-interest. Without external checks, such as incentives, benefits, or legislation, we are, according to this view, in profound conflict with each other and with our natural environment. This view of humanity and of ethical behavior is fundamentally pessimistic. Its conclusion is that we cannot rely on members of our own species in order to protect endangered species unless we make use of the very character traits that endangered them in the first place.

Intrinsic value in wildlife: Why we ought to protect species

Richard Routley, who later changed his last name to Sylvan, argued that positions that only stress the instrumental value of nonhuman species do not provide sufficient ground for environmental ethics. He presented the “last man” argument, a thought experiment in which he asked if the last person on Earth, well knowing that no human being will ever inhabit the planet afterward and equipped with the means to eliminate all life on the planet, would be justified in doing so. Sylvan suggests that most people would intuitively say “no” and call such destructive behavior morally wrong, although no human being would remain to experience the consequences ( Sylvan 1998 ). This suggests that there is value in species independent of their use for humans. Whether or not intrinsic value can exist in anything other than human life, however, is debatable. Unlike economic value, which is measurable, intrinsic value is difficult to express and to prove.

Extensionist environmental ethics

One way of identifying the intrinsic value of nonhumans is to extend traditional moral theory, which concerns itself with interaction between humans, to include members of other species, stressing their similarities to humans. The search for features common to humans and other animals is an attempt at building a particular type of moral community. Most people have no difficulty in recognizing the moral bond between parents and children, for example, or between friends or partners. As we extend moral obligations beyond the boundaries of our immediate environment, we naturally look for features that give an inferential foundation for this extension. Consequently, so-called extensionist arguments ask what qualities give intrinsic value to humans, and then assert that some other beings possess these qualities, too. In the Kantian tradition, this moral criterion is rationality ( Downie 1995 ), and one common justification for valuing animals intrinsically is that some have been shown to possess some rudimentary form of reasoning. Chimpanzees and gorillas have been taught sign language; some predators, such as wolves and lions, have the ability to coordinate hunts; dolphins, whales, and other cetaceans send complex signals that we are only beginning to understand. But basing intrinsic value on these abstract capacities seems to rule out most animals, including most invertebrate species.

Another moral criterion is sentience ( Singer 2001 ). The argument is that because animals share the ability to experience their environment and to suffer, human actions that inflict suffering on animals are morally wrong. Using sentience as the moral criterion does include a wider class of animals within an extended ethical domain, but still restricts it to sentient animals. Plants, fungi, and single-celled organisms are effectively ruled out.

What is common to all extensionist theories is that they take the ego as the point of departure: I am intrinsically valuable because I possess the moral criterion, and I must grant others who possess the criterion the same rights. The problem with this line of argument is obvious: The scope of moral consideration will either extend only to some but not all species or lead to a very demanding code of conduct, since it is then morally wrong for humans to kill individuals of any species, unless justified through an appeal to our own survival. What is more, extensionist arguments focus on individual organisms rather than on whole species. Such individualist approaches allow no moral consideration of animal or plant populations, or of endemic, rare, or endangered species, let alone biotic communities or ecosystems, because entities and aggregations such as these have no apparent psychological experience. Conservationists, however, are concerned with the conservation of species and ecosystems rather than individual animals. Hence it is questionable whether these individualistic approaches can serve as an ethical underpinning for wildlife conservation ( Cafaro and Primack 2001 ).

Holistic environmental ethics

In contrast with individualistic environmental ethicists, other ethicists state that viewing nature as an aggregation of individuals is a distortion that does not appreciate nature's organic, integrated, and dynamic character ( Palmer 2003 ). It is for this reason, among others, that some ethicists argue a completely new ethics is required: Environmental ethics need to challenge the philosophical tradition and to develop arguments that go far beyond simply extending traditional moral arguments ( Sylvan 1998 ). Holistic environmental ethics focus on ethical consideration of ecological wholes ( Palmer 2003 ), which encompass all levels of individuals, aggregations, relationships, and processes. Such non-extensionist approaches, also called naturalistic or biocentric, seek arguments to support the preservation of species, because all species represent unique biological solutions to the problem of survival ( Rolston 2001 ). More diverse biological communities seem to be better able to deal with environmental disturbances; therefore, if we value some species, we arguably should protect the entire system of interdependent species. Examples of such holistic approaches are Aldo Leopold's “land ethic” (1970, Callicott 1998 ) and Rolston's “environmental ethics” (1991). Leopold's essay “The Land Ethic” (1970) is considered by many the foundational work in holistic environmental ethics, although more recent interpretations focus on anthropocentric elements in Leopold's work ( Norton 1996 , Palmer 2003 ). To Leopold, the community rather than the individual organism is the focus of moral consideration, and ecological qualities such as integrity and stability are of primary value. This approach therefore provides arguments for the conservation of species, rather than individual organisms, inasmuch as species play an important role in the stability and integrity of the ecosystem.

Approaches that prioritize the whole over the individual, particularly when the whole is the wild biotic community, are widely viewed as ethically unacceptable or even fascist ( Palmer 2003 ). The focus on the ecological system leads to a picture of human beings, not as vital to the workings of the system, but rather as detrimental to it. Rolston goes so far as to conclude that sometimes the protection of the environment takes precedence over feeding hungry people ( Rolston 2003 ). Thus, wildlife conservators who adopt a biocentric stance see their responsibility as protecting the ecosystem from people whose actions are perceived as harming the natural environment. As a consequence, conservation workers, in their struggle to protect the natural environment, are likely to become antagonized toward people. Such misanthropic positions sharpen the dichotomy of human versus environment and are unlikely to be helpful in balancing the interests of people with the protection of the environment, which lies at the heart of the wildlife conservation challenge.

The debate over intrinsic value has been criticized as being of little use for environmental policymaking ( Light and Katz 1996 ). Whether or not nonhuman entities can have intrinsic value is considered by environmental pragmatists a purely theoretical discussion. The origin of the discussion on intrinsic value may lie embedded in the tradition of Western philosophical thought. Modern thinking is strongly influenced by Descartes (1596–1650), who divided the world into matter and mind, thus creating a dualism that treats humans and their environment as separate entities ( Taliaferro 2001 ). The influence of 17th-century classical science on Western culture is pervasive. Descartes's skeptical, mathematical method underpins modern science, and rationality shapes modern Western thought. The scientific revolution replaced the organic view of nature as a living organism with the mechanistic view of nature as a machine ( Merchant 1980 ). The organic notion of nature carried the dual connotation both of nature as a nurturing mother and of nature as an unpredictable female who causes chaos through natural disasters ( Merchant 1980 ). The increased mechanization that followed in the wake of the new scientific discoveries not only provided a means to control and subordinate nature but also led to a mechanistic worldview emphasizing order and control. Whereas the image of Earth as a living organism had served as a cultural constraint restricting human actions in relation to the environment, the increasingly rationalized world-view resulting from the scientific revolution portrays nature as lifeless and thus sanctions its exploitation ( Merchant 1980 ). The result is a worldview in which humans and nature are separated and in which humans are seen as subjective agents and nature as a passive object. This view makes it difficult to envision people and the natural environment as mutually interdependent. Whereas the dependency of people on their environment is obvious, the natural environment seems to be better off without people.

The oneness of self and its environment

Eastern philosophy, on the other hand, is not based on the mind–matter dichotomy ( Allwright 2002 ) but rather on the principle of harmonious and nonviolent coexistence ( Xianlin et al. 2001 ). Whereas the Western approach to nature has been a violent one focused on conquering nature, the Eastern approach has been characterized by respect for the rhythms, processes, and phenomena of the natural world ( Lai 2001 , Xianlin et al. 2001 ).

An example of the latter approach can be found in the work of Daisaku Ikeda, who is a Buddhist philosopher, author, and president of Soka Gakkai International, a nongovernmental organization and lay Buddhist association with more than 12 million members around the world. Ikeda's approach provides a bridge between Eastern and Western thought that is a valuable contribution to environmental philosophy.

Ikeda's philosophy is based on Buddhist thought, central to which is the concept of dependent origination (also called dependent co-arising). The doctrine of dependent origination expresses the interdependence of all things, meaning that beings or phenomena cannot exist on their own, but exist or occur because of their relationship with other beings and phenomena. In this view, everything in the world comes into existence in response to internal causes and external conditions; in other words, nothing can exist independent of other things or arise in isolation. As Ikeda explains in “Dialogues on Eastern Religion” ( Xianlin et al. 2001 ), “According to this view, when one particular cause or set of causes exists then a certain result comes about; when one entity comes into being, so does another entity” (p. 9).

This concept of dependent origination is compatible with the biological concept of symbiosis. Each human being exists within the context of interrelationships that include not only other human beings but all living beings and the natural world. Interestingly, Ikeda does not consider this relationship as one-sided (i.e., human beings depend on the natural environment in order to flourish), but as a mutual relationship of interdependence. To give a better understanding of this idea, Ikeda explains that according to Buddhist ontology life can be described in terms of 10 factors ( Ikeda 1994 ). The first three factors—appearance, nature, and entity—describe life from a static perspective; the next six—power, influence, internal cause, external cause, latent effect, and manifest effect—describe the dynamic functions of life. Power and influence refer, respectively, to life's inherent capacity to act and to the action that is produced when this inherent power is activated. Internal cause, external cause, latent effect, and manifest effect describe how causality links each phenomenon to its environment. Each individual phenomenon contains an internal, latent cause or disposition, which simultaneously contains a latent effect. In the right conditions, this latent internal cause is activated or triggered. External cause thus provides the link between the individual phenomenon and its surroundings. The external conditions cause a change in the internal cause, which in turn results in a change of the latent effect. The manifest effect is the physical result of the action, which arises as a result of the internal cause. Thus the individual and the external world are interlinked through a network of causality. Internal cause and latent effect are simultaneous; the one is contained in the other. The manifest effect, however, often appears later in time. The 10th factor, consistency from beginning to end, refers to the integration of all factors. They are not in themselves separate but are all different aspects of the same phenomenon. If we consider the first three factors as referring to entity and the remaining factors as referring to the function of this entity, “consistency from beginning to end” refers to the unity of an entity and its function; they are inseparable ( Ikeda 1994 ).

The 10 factors together represent the oneness of the material and the spiritual aspect of life. Appearance represents the physical, nature the spiritual aspect of life; internal cause and latent effect refer to the spiritual, because they lie dormant within life; manifest effect, on the other hand, is perceivable in the physical world and thus refers to the material aspect of life. Thus, unlike Western thought, which is underpinned by the dualism of mind and body, Ikeda's philosophy is informed by the “non-dualities” of Buddhist thought: that is, the oneness of body and mind; the oneness of the internal and the external; the oneness of cause and effect; and the oneness of life and its environment ( Ikeda 1994 ).

The idea of the oneness of life and its environment is of particular interest to environmental ethics. As used by Ikeda, the term environment does not denote the whole natural world; rather, it refers to the fact that each living being has its own unique environment.” In this sense, the formation of one's environment coincides with that person's birth into this world” ( Ikeda 1994 , p. 144). Thus, on the most fundamental level, life and environment, sentient beings and nonsentient beings, are inseparable ( Ikeda 1994 ). Ikeda explains the Japanese term for this concept, esho funi, as follows: shō is short for shōhō, which refers to the individual life; e stands for ehō, the environment, which supports the individual. Funi means “two but not two,” referring to the impossibility of separating the two, individual and environment. The individual life influences its environment but at the same time is dependent on it ( Toynbee and Ikeda 1982 ). To explain, Ikeda uses the analogy of a body and its shadow: The body creates the shadow, and when the body moves, the shadow changes. But in a sense the shadow also creates the body, because the absence of the shadow means that there is no bodily form. Similarly, the individual receives form and identity through the environment, and vice versa ( Ikeda 1982 ). The functioning of internal cause, latent effect, external cause, and manifest effect forms an intricate network of relationships between the individual and its surroundings. The manifest effect produced by the factors of internal cause, external condition, and latent effect is exhibited both in the individual life and in its environment.

As human beings, we shape our environment, but we are also products of our environment. According to Ikeda, this dialectic is vital for understanding the interrelationships between human existence and the environment. Because individual life and environment are inseparable, the state of the environment is a reflection of the minds of the people who inhabit it. Environmental degradation is thus a reflection of people's ignorance of the true nature of life and the cosmos: the interrelatedness of all things. Actions based on ignorance of the interrelatedness of all phenomena result in a downward spiral of negativity. It gives rise to greed, which drives people to seek the fulfillment of their desires at the cost of others and to seek the destruction of a situation in which their own desires are frustrated. This greed goes beyond the individual level, creating economic disparities between people and countries on a global scale. The avarice of the industrialized nations has deprived people in developing countries of the conditions by which their basic needs can be met, and the greed of the human race is undermining the right of other living beings to exist. Awareness of the fabric of relatedness, on the other hand, gives rise to the desire for mutually supportive coexistence with others and with the natural environment.

And if we wish to describe the mutual relations that exist between human beings and the environment in these terms, we would say that the living self depends upon the environment for its existence. That is, human beings depend on the workings of the environment or natural ecological conditions for their growth and development. And conversely, as indicated by the statement above that “without life there is no environment,” the environment must wait for the activities of human beings in order to take on a particular shape or undergo changes. Human beings thus play a key role in the creation of a particular environment, and must bear the responsibility for such creation. ( Xianlin et al. 2001 , p. 19)

According to Ikeda, dependent origination, the interdependency of all things and all phenomena, manifests the ordering principle of the cosmos. The failure to recognize the interdependence and interrelatedness of all life is a fundamental delusion, leading to a self-destructive egocentrism that severs the strands of the web of life that support one's own existence. Awareness of the interrelated nature of life, on the other hand, enables a person to overcome instinctive self-love in order to maintain an empathic relationship with others (i.e., other people, other living beings, and nature).

The challenge for environmental ethics is to find a solid rational justification for why nature should be protected from human actions. Arguments that stress the instrumental value other species have for humans provide “practical muscle for conservation where it counts, on the ground” ( Myers 1979a ). However, arguments based on instrumental value imply that it is the conservationist's responsibility to prove that such value exists. Although the conservation of nature in general is widely considered valuable, conservationists find that in practice they have to fight the same battles again and again to protect wild species from harm. There is a perceived need to express the value of wild species in objectively measurable economic terms that can be employed as incentives for wildlife conservation or as arguments against land uses that are harmful to wildlife. This assumption is underpinned by a negative view of humanity, in that it assumes that people in themselves will not conserve nature unless it is clearly to their direct benefit. Humans and nature are seen as being in profound conflict with each other. The concept of the wildlife conservationist is that of a resource manager whose job is to manage natural resources for the benefit of people, but who is fighting an ongoing battle to prove the value of this work.

The existence of intrinsic value in nature, on the other hand, would free conservationists of the obligation to prove that there is value in conserving a particular species. Although it is generally accepted that human life is intrinsically valuable, the possibility of intrinsic value in nonhuman life forms a large part of the environmental ethics debate. Extensionist approaches, which aim to define moral criteria on which such value can be based, are problematic for wildlife managers because they consider individual organisms, not species and ecosystems. By drawing directly from ecological concepts rather than from a human-centered frame of reference, philosophers such as Leopold, Rolston, and others call for a rethinking of our moral framework. Nonetheless, biocentric approaches to environmental ethics can be seen as implying the prioritization of nonhuman life over human life, thus sharpening the dichotomy between humans and the natural environment. The human-versus-nature dualism that underpins both the instrumental and the intrinsic value approaches is unhelpful to wildlife conservation and management, which are concerned with balancing both social and environmental goals.

It is not surprising that the endeavor of providing a rational ethical foundation for conservation is proving difficult, considering that the Western worldview, which has become increasingly influential on a global scale, has for centuries seen the conquest and subjection of nature as its greatest challenge. In contrast, the traditional Eastern view sees humanity as part of nature, not as a rival ( Ikeda 1994 , p. 144). Ikeda suggests that the differing attitudes toward nature may be grounded in the differences between the Eastern and Western views of life itself.

In the tradition of Buddhist thought, Ikeda's exposition of the theories of dependent origination and the oneness of life and its environment transcends the man–nature dualism. This approach provides a bridge between environmental ethics and the resolution of practical environmental problems. Ikeda's work does not in itself constitute an environmental ethic. However, the concepts of dependent origination and the oneness of life and environment provide an ample platform for developing such an ethic. To Ikeda, ethics are not a matter of timeless rules that can be applied to particular situations. Rather, ethics depend on a sensitivity toward the principle of dependent origination. Consequently, Ikeda's aim is not the development of an abstract theory but rather the empowerment of the individual to lead “a contributive way of life…based on an awareness of the interdependent nature of our lives—of the relationships that link us to others and our environment” ( Ikeda 2002 ).

The modern conservation paradigm, conservation for and with people, requires that we overcome the dualism of human versus nature, which creates antagonism between conservationists and other people. Ikeda's philosophy provides a basis for a conservation philosophy that sees the conservationist not as a defender of the natural world against the harmful impact of human actions but as one who realizes the interdependences both between people and between people and nature, and who strives to awaken such awareness in others in order to achieve a better future for all.

Acknowledgements

Tim Dunne, Les Underhill, David Benatar, John Paterson, and Liz Komen read earlier drafts of this paper.

Allwright P . 2002 . Basics of Buddhism. Buckinghamshire (United Kingdom): Taplow Press.

Cafaro PJ Primack RB . 2001 . Ethical issues in biodiversity protection. Pages. 593 - 555 . in Levin SA, ed. Encyclopedia of Biodiversity, vol. 2. San Diego: Academic Press.

Callicott JB . 1998 . The conceptual foundations of the land ethic. Pages. 101 - 123 . in Zimmerman ME, Callicott JB, Sessions G, Warren KJ, Clark J, eds. Environmental Philosophy: From Animal Rights to Radical Ecology. Englewood Cliffs (NJ): Prentice-Hall.

Child G . 1970 . Wildlife utilisation and management in Botswana. Biological Conservation . 3 : 18 - 22 .

Downie RS . 1995 . Kantian ethics. Pages. 438 - 439 . in Honderich T, ed. The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford (United Kingdom): Oxford University Press.

Ehrlich P Ehrlich A . 1982 . Extinction: The Causes and Consequences of the Disappearance of Species. London: Gollancz.

Fisher JA . 2001 . Aesthetics. Pages. 265 - 274 . in Jamieson D, ed. A Companion to Environmental Philosophy. Oxford (United Kingdom): Blackwell.

Ikeda D . 1982 . Life—An Enigma, a Precious Jewel. New York: Kodansha International.

Ikeda D . 1994 . Unlocking the Mysteries of Birth and Death: Buddhism in the Contemporary World. London: Warner.

Ikeda D . 2002 . The Challenge of Global Empowerment: Education for a Sustainable Future. (3 November 2005; www.sgi.org/english/Features/quarterly/0210/proposal.htm ).

Kangwana K Mako RO . 2001 . Conservation, livelihoods and the intrinsic value of wildlife. Pages. 148 - 159 . in Hulme D, Murphree M, eds. African Wildlife and Livelihoods: The Promise and Performance of Community Conservation. Oxford (United Kingdom): James Currey.

Lai KL . 2001 . Classical China. Pages. 21 - 36 . in Jamieson D, ed. A Companion to Environmental Philosophy. Oxford (United Kingdom): Blackwell.

Leopold A . 1970 . A Sand County Almanac: With Essays on Conservation from Round River. New York: Ballantine.

Light A Katz E . eds. 1996 . Environmental Pragmatism . London : Routledge .

Google Scholar

Google Preview

Mauney G. . 2004 . Uukwaluudhi conservancy—a royal dream becomes reality.In Conservation and the Environment in Namibia 2004–2005, special issue, Travel News: 6–7.

Merchant C . 1980 . The Death of Nature: Women, Ecology, and the Scientific Revolution. San Francisco: Harper and Row.

Myers N . 1979a . The Sinking Ark: A New Look at the Problem of Disappearing Species. Oxford (United Kingdom): Pergamon Press.

Myers N . 1979b . Conserving our global stock. Environment . 21 : 25 - 33 .

Myers N . 1983 . A Wealth of Wild Species. Boulder (CO): Westview.

Newmark WD Leonard N Sariko HI Gamassa DM . 1993 . Conservation attitudes of local people living adjacent to five protected areas in Tanzania. Biological Conservation . 63 : 177 - 183 .

Norton B . 1996 . The constancy of Leopold's land ethic. Pages. 84 - 102 . in Light A, Katz E, eds. Environmental Pragmatism. London: Routledge.

Palmer C . 2003 . An overview of environmental ethics. Pages. 15 - 37 . in Light A, Rolston H, eds. Environmental Ethics: An Anthology. Oxford (United Kingdom): Blackwell.

Rolston H . 1991 . Environmental ethics values in and duties to the natural world. Pages. 73 - 96 . in Bormann FH, Kellert SR, eds. Ecology, Economics, Ethics: The Broken Circle. New Haven (CT): Yale University Press.

Rolston H . 2001 . Biodiversity. Pages. 403 - 415 . in Jamieson D, ed. A Companion to Environmental Philosophy. Oxford (United Kingdom): Blackwell.

Rolston H . 2003 . Feeding people versus saving nature?. Pages. 451 - 462 . in Light A, Rolston H, eds. Environmental Ethics: An Anthology. Oxford (United Kingdom): Blackwell.

[SCBD] Secretariat of the Convention on Biological Diversity . 2003 . Handbook of the Convention on Biological Diversity. Montreal: SCBD.

Singer P . 2001 . Animals. Pages. 416 - 425 . in Jamieson D, ed. A Companion to Environmental Philosophy. Oxford (United Kingdom): Blackwell.

Sylvan R . 1998 . Is there a need for a new, an environmental, ethic?. Pages. 17 - 25 . in Zimmermann ME, ed. Environmental Philosophy from Animal Rights to Radical Ecology. Upper Saddle River (NJ): Prentice-Hall.

Taliaferro C . 2001 . Early modern philosophy. Pages. 130 - 145 . in Jamieson D, ed. A Companion to Environmental Philosophy. Oxford (United Kingdom): Blackwell.

Toynbee A Ikeda D . 1982 . Wähle das Leben: Ein Dialog [Choose Life: A Dialogue]. Düsseldorf (Germany): Claassen.

[WCED] World Commission on Environment and Development . 1987 . Our Common Future. Oxford (United Kingdom): Oxford University Press.

Xianlin J Zhongxin J Ikeda D . 2001 . Dialogues on Eastern wisdom (1). Journal of Oriental Studies . 11 : 2 - 86 .

Author notes

Month: Total Views:
November 2016 1
December 2016 3
January 2017 79
February 2017 183
March 2017 240
April 2017 115
May 2017 57
June 2017 23
July 2017 18
August 2017 92
September 2017 158
October 2017 172
November 2017 225
December 2017 923
January 2018 1,042
February 2018 1,298
March 2018 2,025
April 2018 2,198
May 2018 1,848
June 2018 1,135
July 2018 1,076
August 2018 1,089
September 2018 1,137
October 2018 1,154
November 2018 1,641
December 2018 1,399
January 2019 1,276
February 2019 1,390
March 2019 1,674
April 2019 1,796
May 2019 1,736
June 2019 1,366
July 2019 1,237
August 2019 1,313
September 2019 1,069
October 2019 811
November 2019 668
December 2019 579
January 2020 598
February 2020 754
March 2020 688
April 2020 889
May 2020 510
June 2020 669
July 2020 303
August 2020 241
September 2020 520
October 2020 594
November 2020 401
December 2020 383
January 2021 366
February 2021 493
March 2021 482
April 2021 448
May 2021 317
June 2021 313
July 2021 233
August 2021 290
September 2021 312
October 2021 334
November 2021 443
December 2021 289
January 2022 349
February 2022 339
March 2022 471
April 2022 426
May 2022 505
June 2022 411
July 2022 381
August 2022 168
September 2022 264
October 2022 280
November 2022 235
December 2022 243
January 2023 246
February 2023 206
March 2023 215
April 2023 248
May 2023 286
June 2023 146
July 2023 164
August 2023 134
September 2023 207
October 2023 229
November 2023 233
December 2023 184
January 2024 183
February 2024 198
March 2024 394
April 2024 388
May 2024 244
June 2024 158

Email alerts

Citing articles via.

  • Recommend to your Library

Affiliations

  • Online ISSN 1525-3244
  • Copyright © 2024 American Institute of Biological Sciences
  • About Oxford Academic
  • Publish journals with us
  • University press partners
  • What we publish
  • New features  
  • Open access
  • Institutional account management
  • Rights and permissions
  • Get help with access
  • Accessibility
  • Advertising
  • Media enquiries
  • Oxford University Press
  • Oxford Languages
  • University of Oxford

Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the University's objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide

  • Copyright © 2024 Oxford University Press
  • Cookie settings
  • Cookie policy
  • Privacy policy
  • Legal notice

This Feature Is Available To Subscribers Only

Sign In or Create an Account

This PDF is available to Subscribers Only

For full access to this pdf, sign in to an existing account, or purchase an annual subscription.

Aldo Leopold’s life–work and the scholarship it inspired

  • Review Article
  • Published: 26 March 2020
  • Volume 2 , pages 3–30, ( 2020 )

Cite this article

research papers on land ethic

  • Lin Qi Feng   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0002-8442-9917 1  

We’re sorry, something doesn't seem to be working properly.

Please try refreshing the page. If that doesn't work, please contact support so we can address the problem.

Since its publication in 1949, Aldo Leopold’s A Sand County Almanac , especially “The Land Ethic” essay, has been influential in conservation and environmental circles. In this wide-ranging but limited review, I discussed Leopold’s life and work, including the important concepts he had written about, and briefly survey the secondary literature he inspired in the realms of science, environmental history, environmental ethics, and ecocriticism.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Subscribe and save.

  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or Ebook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime

Price includes VAT (Russian Federation)

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Rent this article via DeepDyve

Institutional subscriptions

research papers on land ethic

Courtesy of the Aldo Leopold Foundation and University of Wisconsin - Madison Archives

research papers on land ethic

Similar content being viewed by others

research papers on land ethic

Aldo Leopold: Connecting Conservation Science, Ethics, Policy, and Practice

research papers on land ethic

The Romantic Pastoral: Snyder’s Ecological Literary Inheritance

research papers on land ethic

Land, ethics, justice, and Aldo Leopold

All references to ASCA are to Leopold ( 1949 ), the original edition of the work.

Meine ( 2010 , p. 503) described the statement as a “firm appeal for self-inquiry.”

All biographical information is drawn from Curt Meine’s biography of Leopold (Meine 2010 ). Leopold ( 1991 ) includes a compact chronology of Leopold’s life, while Leopold ( 2013 ) contains a more complete chronology.

The Yale Forest School was renamed to “Yale School of Forestry” in 1921 with Pinchot’s consent. In 1972 the name was modified to “Yale School of Forestry & Environmental Studies.” From July 1, 2020, the school will change its name to “Yale School of Environment” and establish “The Forest School at the Yale School of the Environment,” which will have a clear identify and separate resources within the School of the Environment (Yale School of Forestry & Environmental Studies 2020 ).

For histories of the progressive conservation movement, see Hays ( 1959 ) and Miller ( 2001 ).

The reconnaissance was a fiasco under Leopold’s inexperienced leadership, but he would acquit himself well in a second reconnaissance in the next year.

Leopold’s success at organizing sportsmen and advancing game protection enabled him to parry, with support from his superior Arthur Ringland, multiple urgent requests from Chief of the Forest Service Henry S. Graves to transfer him to Washington DC (Meine 2010 , pp. 146–147, 152–153) and led to him receiving a congratulatory letter from President Theodore Roosevelt in January 1917 (p. 158).

The eight states were Minnesota, Wisconsin, Michigan, Iowa, Illinois, Indiana, Ohio, and Missouri.

The University of Wisconsin is now known as the University of Wisconsin-Madison, following the merger in 1971 of public universities in Wisconsin to form the University of Wisconsin System (Cronon and Jenkins 1999 , pp. 521–596).

Jack Stark defines the Wisconsin Idea as “the University’s direct contributions to the state: to the government in the forms of serving in office, offering advice about public policy, providing information and exercising technical skill, and to the citizens in the forms of doing research directed at solving problems that are important to the state and conducting outreach activities” ( 1995 , p. 2). A common expression of the Idea is “the boundaries of the University are the boundaries of the state” (pp. 1–2). The Wisconsin Idea was bolstered by the presence of two prominent economists, Richard T. Ely and John R. Commons, who groomed a generation of Wisconsin economists who in turn played critical roles in developing New Deal agricultural policy (Gilbert and Baker 1997 ).

Leopold’s speech delivered at the Arboretum’s dedication ceremony on June 17, 1934 and titled “What Is the University of Wisconsin Arboretum, Wild Life Refuge, and Forest Experiment Preserve?” (Leopold [ 1934 ] 1984) is longer than the subsequent essay “The Arboretum and the University” (Leopold [ 1934 ] 1991a). Both the speech and the essay are available online as appendices to Callicott ( 1999a ).

The Central Sand Plains of Wisconsin is the result of sandy lake deposits of what was once glacial Lake Wisconsin, created during the last part of the Wisconsin Glaciation (c.19,000 or 18,000 before present [BP]) when ice of the Green Bay lobe of the Laurentide Ice Sheet advanced onto the eastern end of the Baraboo Hills, damming the Wisconsin River. The drainage basin of the lake consists of late Cambrian sandstone. The lake itself consisted of a main basin and a few smaller basins, and drained multiple times when the ice dam failed. The last drainage occurred about 18,000 BP (Attig and Carson 2016 ; Clayton and Attig 1989 , pp. 1–7). The Leopold shack is located on the sand plain in the southern part of the Lewiston basin (Attig and Carson 2016 ).

The Leopold family’s restoration activities at the shack left a mark on the Wisconsin landscape (Waller and Rooney 2008 ) and led to establishment of the Leopold Memorial Reserve (Laubach 2014 ; Liegel 1982 ; Liegel 1988 ) and the Leopold-Pine Island Important Bird Area (Aldo Leopold Foundation n.d.-a).

Leopold published a few articles about his trips to Germany ( 1936a , b , c ; [ 1936 ] 2013) and Mexico ( 1937 b; [ 1937b ] 1991).

The comments from Knopf reveal the publisher’s perception of the unusual character of the manuscript and of readers’ expectations:

What we like best is the nature observations, and the more objective narratives and essays. We like less the subjective parts—that is, the philosophical reflections, which are less fresh, and which one reader finds sometimes “fatuous.” The ecological argument everyone finds unconvincing; and as in previous drafts, it is not tied up with the rest of the book.

In short, the book seems unlikely to win approval from readers or to be a successful publication as it now stands, and a more fundamental kind of revision is needed than the detailed, page-by-page comments you asked [for] would suggest (cited in Meine 2010 , p. 509).

Reviewers of ASCA lauded Leopold’s observation powers, skillful writing, his expansive concern for nature, as well as Schwartz’s illustrations. Reviews can be found in the Aldo Leopold Archives, 10-6 box 5 folder 5, http://digital.library.wisc.edu/1711.dl/aldoleopold.alsandcounty.i0005 .

Guha ( 1989 ) observed that the radical environmental movement in the USA possessed characteristics unique to the country and was therefore unsuitable for universal application.

For a review of Ian McHarg’s work, see the special issue of Socio-Ecological Practice Research , 1, 3-4, October 2019, titled Design With Nature at 50: Retrospect and Prospect ( https://link.springer.com/journal/42532/1/3 ).

Essays on conservation published in Round River were inserted into an enlarged version of ASCA , constituting its Part III while Part III of the original became Part IV. The enlarged edition was published as A Sand County Almanac with Other Essays on Conservation from Round River by Oxford University Press in 1966. The paperback versions of the original and enlarged editions were, respectively, released in 1968 by Oxford University Press and in 1970 by Sierra Club/Ballantine Books (Callicott 2014 , p. 21).

This collection was first published in 1990 as Aldo Leopold’s Wilderness by Stackpole Books.

Leopold’s youngest child Estella Jr. recalled: “We always cringed…when we heard and read about how in 1832 Chief Blackhawk put his Sauk people, women and children, on a raft just below the present Sauk City on the Wisconsin River only to have federal troopers shoot them one by one with their rifles from the south bank. I always hated to think about that tragedy, which is now commemorated by a bronze historical plaque marking the place by the river where the ambush occurred. Chief Blackhawk himself escaped and hid for a while in the hills. We used to pass that site every weekend on our way to and from the Shack. It always gave me sobering thoughts” (Leopold 2016 , p. 9).

Whyte contrasted Leopold’s individualistic ethic with the work of Deborah McGregor, an Anishinaabe writer who also works on environmental issues.

In the chapter Savoy compared Leopold’s land ethic with her father Willard Savoy’s novel Alien Land (Savoy 1949 ).

The situation, we now know, was more complex than what Leopold’s account suggests. Worster ( 1993 , pp. 45–46) pointed out that bluegrass was inadvertently imported by immigrants from Europe.

According to Flader, “Leopold used the expression ‘thinking like a mountain’ to characterize objective or ecological thinking; it should not be viewed as personification” ([1974] 1994 , pp. 1, fn 1).

See the discussion on Flader’s Thinking Like a Mountain ([1974] 1994 ) in Sect.  4.2 .

“The so-called ‘balance of nature’ is simply a name for the assumed tendency of the population curves of various species in an undisturbed plant and animal community to keep each other horizontal. The growth of biological knowledge trends strongly to show that while population curves may oscillate about a horizontal median, a single curve seldom or never stays horizontal from year to year even in virgin terrain. Fluctuation in numbers is nearly universal” (Leopold [1933] 1986 , p. 26).

For a discussion of the shared conservation history of Canada and the USA, see Sandlos ( 2013 ).

For a contemporary review of ecology, see Allee et al. ( 1949 , pp. 1–72).

“I am trying to teach you that this alphabet of ‘natural objects’ (soils and rivers, birds and beasts) spells out a story, which he who runs may read—if he knows how. Once you learn to read the land, I have no fear of what you will do to it, or with it. And I know many pleasant things it will do to you” (Leopold [ 1947 ] 1991b, p. 337).

Leopold would consent to enter a church only on rare occasions, his own marriage being one. As a parent Leopold did not say a word on the subject of religion. Even though he hid his doubts about the Church for the most part, his children could sense that he took a dim view of it (Meine 2010 , p. 376).

“ Noumenal means apprehended by the mind ; and the characteristic property of the things of the noumenal world is that they cannot be comprehended by the same method by which the things of the phenomenal world are comprehended . We may speculate about the things of the noumenal world; we may discover them by a process of reasoning, and by means of analogy; we may feel them, and enter into some sort of communion with them; but we can neither see, hear, touch, weigh, measure them; nor can we photograph them or decompose them into chemical elements or number their vibrations. The noumenal world , or the world of causes, is for us the world of metaphysical facts” (Ouspensky 1920 , p. 181, italics in original). Leopold was too generous in his interpretation of Ouspensky’s book, attributing planetary temporal and spatial scales and hierarchical organization of different parts of the earth to it (Callicott 2014 , pp. 161–162).

Leopold identified the key species of a particular location that signifies its noumenon, noting that “the grouse is the numenon [sic] of the north woods, the blue jay of the hickory groves, the whisky jack of the muskegs, the piñonero of the juniper foothills,” the bear of the Escudilla Mountain in Arizona, and the Thick-billed Parrot of the Sierra Madre Occidental in Mexico (1949, pp. 133–141), and used the music metaphor to describe the noumenon of the hills of the Rio Gavilan (pp. 149–150).

On husbandry, Leopold wrote: “Government can't raise crops, maintain small scattered structures, administer small scattered areas, or bring to bear on small local matters that combination of solicitude, foresight, and skill which we call husbandry. Husbandry watches no clock, knows no season of cessation, and for the most part is paid for in love, not dollars” (Leopold [1942] 1991 , p. 298).

Leopold was warned by former student Douglas Wade ( 1944 ) about the subtle inclinations to socialization he displayed in a couple of articles published in The Audubon Magazine (Leopold [1942] 1991 , p. 298; Leopold [1944] 2013 ).

This occurrence of Leopold’s “land ethic” was identified by Warren ( 2016 , p. 149), although she cites it as part of an accompanying letter.

Making the case for a new, an environmental, ethic, Richard Sylvan ([ 1973 ] 2001) noted that Leopold’s prescription for extending traditional morality to include land is inadequate because an ethic that is embedded in the Western super ethic of human dominion over the environment and of the liberal tradition of not causing harm to human others and to oneself would be ineffectual in preventing environmental harm. Sylvan’s assessment suggests he overlooked Leopold’s statement about how “a land ethic changes the role of Homo sapiens from conqueror of the land-community to plain member and citizen of it” (Leopold 1949 , p. 204). In the first article on environmental ethics in Ethics Rolston ( 1975 ) interpreted Leopold’s land ethic as calling for the preservation of integrity of ecosystems and used it to introduce the idea of “ecological ethics,” or ethics that are thoroughly informed by ecological principles. Rolston indicated the novelty of the ecological turn in philosophy during the 1960s and 1970s when he discussed the arresting novelty of “ecological conscience”: “The puzzlement lies neither in the noun nor in the by now familiar modifier, but in their operation on each other. We are comfortable with a Christian or humanist ethic, but the moral noun does not regularly take a scientific adjective…” (1975, p. 93).

Callicott taught what appeared to be the first environmental philosophy course in the USA (Callicott 1987a , p. vii).

According to Callicott ( 2014 , p. 46), “…‘The Land Ethic’ is the crowning part—the capstone essay, the climax, the denouement. The land ethic represents the axiological (ethical and aesthetical) and normative (practical moral) implications of an evolutionary-ecological worldview, which is gradually exposed and promulgated in the preceding parts of the book. In [ ASCA ]’s Part I, readers are introduced to an evolutionary-ecological worldview—circumspectly and indirectly through narrative description, vicarious sensory experience, and imaginative engagement. In [ ASCA ]’s Part II, readers are introduced to an evolutionary-ecological worldview also by means of narrative accounts of the author’s experience on his own journey of discovery and conversion, but more directly, more urgently, and certainly more confrontationally than in Part I.” See also Callicott ( 2005 ); Callicott ( 2011 ); Callicott ( 2012 ).

In their interpretation of the Darwinian context of the land ethic, Callicott (1987b, pp. 188–189; 2001, p. 205) and Norton (2005, pp. 69–70) refer to these sentences in “The Land Ethic”: “This extension of ethics, so far studied only by philosophers, is actually a process in ecological evolution. Its sequences may be described in ecological as well as in philosophical terms. An ethic, ecologically, is a limitation on freedom of action in the struggle for existence. An ethic, philosophically, is a differentiation of social from anti-social conduct. These are two definitions of one thing. The thing has its origin in the tendency of interdependent individuals or groups to evolve modes of co-operation” (Leopold 1949 , p. 202).

For criticisms of and improvements on Callicott’s analysis of Hume’s ideas as foundation of Leopold’s land ethic, see Welchman ( 2009 ) and references therein.

It is easy to see from Callicott’s early writing why Regan levied this serious charge: “The preciousness of individual deer, as of any other specimen, is inversely proportional to the population of the species. Environmentalists, however reluctantly and painfully, do not omit to apply the same logic to their own kind. As omnivores, the population of human beings should, perhaps, be roughly twice that of bears, allowing for differences of size. A global population of more than four billion persons and showing no signs of an orderly decline presents an alarming prospect to humanists, but it is at present a global disaster (the more per capita prosperity, indeed, the more disastrous it appears) for the biotic community” (Callicott 1980 , p. 326).

Luna wrote:

…These extreme extrapolations pay no heed to Leopold’s deep concern for his aging mother. They do not reflect the fact that he always avoided putting anyone in an uncomfortable or embarrassing position. Never would he talk down to a person and he treated people in menial positions with the same consideration and courtesy as he would the most exalted.

Rather than interpreting the concept of the land ethic as an indication of disregard for the individual in favor of the species or the ecosystem, my view is quite different. I see the concept as the outgrowth and extension of his deep personal concern for the individual. Accepting the idea that the cooperations and competitions in the human society are eased and facilitated by concern for others, he saw that the same consideration extended to other parts of the ecosystem and would tend to add integrity, beauty, and stability to the whole. Leopold ( 1987 , p. viii).

“And if there be, indeed, a special nobility inherent in the human race—a special cosmic value, distinctive from and superior to all other life—by what token shall it be manifest? By a society decently respectful of its own and all other life, capable of inhabiting the earth without defiling it? Or by a society like that of John Burroughs’ potato bug, which exterminated the potato, and thereby exterminated itself?” (Leopold [ 1923 ] 1991b, p. 97).

Norton ( 1988 , p. 95) surmised that Leopold was exposed to Hadley ( 1913 ) through a review in the Yale Review , which Leopold regularly read according to biographer Meine (Norton 1988 , en 3). Indeed, the line that Leopold misquoted, replacing “right” with “truth,” appeared in the review: “[The force of the scientific discoveries] has even given us the basis, says Mr. Hadley, of ‘a new spiritual philosophy of life.’ For the scientific man to-day ‘believes, as the very essence of his theory, that the right is that which will prevail in the long run.’ The adoption of this hypothesis is the most important mark of distinction between us and our fathers” (Sherman 1914 , p. 385).

Norton and Callicott have sparred over whether Leopold was influenced by pragmatist philosophy (Callicott 2014 , pp. 171–177; Callicott et al. 2009 ; Callicott et al. 2011a ; Norton 2011 ; Stephens 2018 ).

The name has entered the lexicon of the English-speaking world, an example dictionary definition being “a person likened to the character George Babbitt,  esp.  a materialistic, complacent businessman who conforms unthinkingly to the views and standards of his social set” (Oxford English Dictionary Online  2019 ).

Aldo Leopold Foundation (2017) Still searching for Leopold’s voice. https://www.aldoleopold.org/post/still-searching-leopolds-voice/ . Accessed 13 Feb 2020

Aldo Leopold Foundation (n.d.-a) Leopold-pine island important bird area. https://www.aldoleopold.org/visit/the-land/leopold-pine-island-iba/ . Accessed 13 Feb 2020

Aldo Leopold Foundation (n.d.-b) Leopold family. https://www.aldoleopold.org/about/aldo-leopold/leopold-family/ . Accessed 13 Feb 2020

Allee WC, Emerson AE, Park O, Park T, Schmidt KP (1949) Principles of animal ecology. W.B. Saunders Co., Philadelphia

Google Scholar  

Anderson R (2002) Coon Valley days. Wis Acad Rev 48:42–48

Apfelbaum SI, Haney AW (2010) Restoring ecological health to your land. Island Press, Washington

Attig J, Carson E (2016) Geologic history of the Wisconsin river. https://www.aldoleopold.org/post/geologic-history-wisconsin-river/ . Accessed 4 Oct 2019

Balaev M, Glotfelty C (2012) The formation of a field: ecocriticism in America—an interview with Cheryll Glotfelty PMLA 127:607–616. www.jstor.org/stable/41616853

Barbour IG (ed) (1973) Western man and environmental ethics: attitudes toward nature and technology. Addison-Wesley Pub. Co., Reading

Barillas W (1996) Aldo Leopold and midwestern pastoralism American studies 37:61–81. www.jstor.org/stable/40642821

Barillas WD (2006) The Midwestern pastoral: place and landscape in literature of the American heartland. Ohio Univ. Press, Athens

Berkes F, Doubleday NC, Cumming GS (2012) Aldo Leopold’s land health from a resilience point of view: self-renewal capacity of social-ecological systems. EcoHealth 9:278–287

Binkley D, Moore M, Romme W, Brown P (2006) Was Aldo Leopold right about the Kaibab deer herd? Ecosystems 9:227–241. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10021-005-0100-z

Article   Google Scholar  

Boulding KE (1966) The economics of the coming spaceship Earth. In: Jarrett H (ed) Environmental quality in a growing economy. Resources for the Future/Johns Hopkins University Press, Baltimore, pp 3–14

Bradley NL, Leopold AC, Ross J, Huffaker W (1999) Phenological changes reflect climate change in Wisconsin. Proc Natl Acad Sci 96:9701–9704. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.96.17.9701

Brennan A, Lo Y-S (2016) Environmental ethics. In: Zalta EN (ed) The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/ethics-environmental/

Budolfson MB (2014) Why the standard interpretation of the land ethic is mistaken. Environ Ethics 36:443–453

Callicott JB (1980) Animal liberation: a triangular affair. Environ Ethics 2:311–338

Callicott JB (1982) Traditional American Indian and Western European attitudes toward nature environmental ethics 4:292–318. http://www.secure.pdcnet.org/enviroethics/content/enviroethics_1982_0004_0004_0293_0318

Callicott JB (ed) (1987a) Companion to A Sand County Almanac : interpretive and critical essays. University of Wisconsin Press, Madison

Callicott JB (1987b) The conceptual foundations of the land ethic. In: Callicott JB (ed) Companion to A Sand County Almanac : interpretive and critical essays. University of Wisconsin Press, Madison, pp 186–217

Callicott JB (1989) In defense of the land ethic: essays in environmental philosophy. State University of New York Press, Albany

Callicott JB (1992) Aldo Leopold’s metaphor. In: Costanza R, Norton BG, Haskell BD (eds) Ecosystem health: new goals for environmental management. Island Press, Washington, pp 42–56

Callicott JB (1993) The search for an environmental ethic. In: Regan T (ed) Matters of life and death: new introductory essays in moral philosophy. McGraw-Hill, New York, pp 322–382

Callicott JB (1999a) The arboretum and the university: the speech and the essay. Transactions of the Wisconsin Academy of Sciences, Arts, and Letters, vol 87, pp 5–22. http://digicoll.library.wisc.edu/cgi-bin/WI/WI-idx?type=article&did=WI.WT1999.JBCallicott&id=WI.WT1999&isize=XL

Callicott JB (1999b) Beyond the land ethic: more essays in environmental philosophy. State University of New York Press, Albany

Callicott JB (1999c) Holistic environmental ethics and the problem of ecofascism. In: Beyond the land ethic: more essays in environmental philosophy. State University of New York Press, Albany, pp 59–76

Callicott JB (2000) Aldo Leopold and the foundations of ecosystem management. J For 98:5–13

Callicott JB (2001) The land ethic. In: Jamieson D (ed) A companion to environmental philosophy. pp 204–217. https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/abs/10.1002/9780470751664.ch14

Callicott JB (2002) From the balance of nature to the flux of nature: the land ethic in a time of change. In: Knight RL, Riedel S (eds) Aldo Leopold and the ecological conscience. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 90–105

Callicott JB (2005) Turning the whole soul: the educational dialectic of A Sand County Almanac . Worldviews Glob Relig Cult Ecol 9:365–384. https://doi.org/10.1163/156853505774841678

Callicott JB (2008) Leopold’s land aesthetic. In: Carlson A, Lintott S (eds) Nature, aesthetics, and environmentalism: from beauty to duty. Columbia University Press, New York, pp 105–118

Callicott JB (2011) The worldview concept and Aldo Leopold’s project of ‘world view’ remediation. J Stud Relig Nat Cult 5:510–528. https://doi.org/10.1558/jsrnc.v5i4.510

Callicott JB (2012) A Sand County Almanac: an evolutionary-ecological worldview. In: Vaz SG (ed) Environment: why read the classics? Greenleaf Publishing, Sheffield, pp 36–71

Callicott JB (2014) Thinking like a planet: the land ethic and the earth ethic. Oxford University Press, New York

Callicott JB (2015) The centennial return of stewardship to the Ecological Society of America. In: Rozzi R, Chapin FS III, Callicott JB, Pickett STA, Power ME, Armesto JJ, May RH Jr (eds) Earth stewardship: linking ecology and ethics in theory and practice. Springer, Dordrecht, pp 161–171

Callicott JB, Nelson MP (2004) American Indian environmental ethics: an Ojibwa case study. Prentice Hall, Upper Saddle River

Callicott JB, Grove-Fanning W, Rowland J, Baskind D, French RH, Walker K (2009) Was Aldo Leopold a pragmatist? Rescuing Leopold from the imagination of Bryan Norton. Environ Values 18:453–486. http://www.jstor.org/stable/30302398

Callicott JB, Grove-Fanning W, Rowland J, Baskind D, French RH, Walker K (2011a) Reply to Norton, re: Aldo Leopold and pragmatism. Environ Values 20:17–22

Callicott JB et al (2011b) The other in A Sand County Almanac : Aldo Leopold’s animals and his wild-animal ethic. Environ Ethics 33:115–146

Caputi J (2011) Feeding green fire. J Study Relig Nat Cult 5:410–436. https://doi.org/10.1558/jsrnc.v5i4.410

Carpenter FI (1938) Tristram the transcendent the New England quarterly 11:501–523. http://www.jstor.org/stable/360789

Carson R (1962) Silent spring. Houghton Mifflin, Boston

Clayton L, Attig JW (1989) Glacial Lake Wisconsin. Memoir, vol 173. Geological Society of America. https://doi.org/10.1130/mem173

Commoner B (1972) The closing circle: confronting the environmental crisis. Cape, London

Coufal JE (1989) The land ethic question. J Forest 87:22–24. https://doi.org/10.1093/jof/87.6.22

Court FE (2012) Pioneers of ecological restoration : the people and legacy of the University of Wisconsin Arboretum. University of Wisconsin Press, Madison

Cronon W (1990) Landscape and home: environmental traditions in Wisconsin. Wis Mag Hist 74:82–105. https://doi.org/10.2307/4636316

Cronon ED, Jenkins JW (1999) The University of Wisconsin: a history, vol 4; renewal to revolution (1945–1971). University of Wisconsin Press, Madison. http://digital.library.wisc.edu/1711.dl/UW.UWHist19451971v4

Cushman GT (2013) Guano and the opening of the pacific world: a global ecological history. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

Darwin C ([1871] 2009) The descent of man and selection in relation to sex. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511703829

Darwin C, Costa JT ([1859] 2009) The annotated origin: a facsimile of the first edition of on the origin of species. Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Mass

Dicks H (2014) Aldo Leopold and the ecological imaginary: the balance, the pyramid, and the round river. Environ Philos 11:175–209. https://doi.org/10.5840/envirophil20149912

Disch R (1970) The ecological conscience: values for survival. A spectrum book. Prentice-Hall, Englewood Cliffs

Dixon B (2016) Deriving moral considerability from Leopold’s A Sand County Almanac . Ethics Policy Environ. https://doi.org/10.1080/21550085.2016.1195191

Dixon B (2017) Value pluralism and consistency maximisation in the writings of Aldo Leopold: moving beyond Callicott’s interpretations of the land ethic. Environ Values 26:269–295. https://doi.org/10.3197/096327117X14913285800661

Dunsky S, Dunsky A, Steinke D (2011) Green fire: Aldo Leopold and a land ethic for our time. Aldo Leopold Foundation, Baraboo

Egler F (1989) Conservation biology in historical perspective. Conserv Biol 3:99–100. http://www.jstor.org/stable/2385999

Ehrlich PR (1968) The population bomb. Ballantine Books, New York

Ellwood ER, Temple SA, Primack RB, Bradley NL, Davis CC (2013) Record-breaking early flowering in the eastern United States. PLoS ONE 8:e53788–e53788. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0053788

Elton C (1927) Animal ecology. MacMillan, New York

Flader SL (1979) Leopold’s ‘Some fundamentals of conservation’: a commentary. Environ Ethics 1:143–148

Flader SL (1987a) Aldo Leopold and the evolution of a land ethic. In: Tanner T (ed) Aldo Leopold: the man and his legacy. Soil Conservation Society of America, Ankeny, Iowa, pp 3–24

Flader SL (1987b) Aldo Leopold’s sand country. In: Callicott JB (ed) Companion to A Sand County Almanac : interpretive and critical essays. University of Wisconsin Press, Madison, pp 40–62

Flader SL (1994) Aldo Leopold and the evolution of ecosystem management. In: Covington WW, DeBano LF (eds) Sustainable ecological systems: implementing an ecological approach to land management. USDA Forest Service general technical report rocky mountain, vol 247. U.S. Department of Agriculture, Forest Service, Rocky Mountain Forest and Range Experiment Station, Fort Collins, CO, pp 15–19

Flader SL (2011) Aldo Leopold and the land ethic: an argument for sustaining soils. In: Sauer TJ, Norman JM, Sivakumar MVK (eds) Sustaining soil productivity in response to global climate change. Wiley, Hoboken. pp 43–65. http://dx.doi.org/10.1002/9780470960257.ch4

Flader SL, Callicott JB (1991) Introduction. In: Flader SL, Callicott JB (eds) The river of the mother of god and other essays. University of Wisconsin Press, Madison, pp 3–31

Flader SL ([1974] 1994) Thinking like a mountain: Aldo Leopold and the evolution of an ecological attitude toward deer, wolves, and forests. University of Wisconsin Press, Madison

Flaspohler DJ, Meine C (2006) Planning for wildness: aldo Leopold’s report on Huron Mountain Club. J For 104:32–42

Forbes W (ed) (forthcoming) Revisiting Aldo Leopold’s land ethic: emerging cultures of sustainability. Stephen F. Austin University Press, Nacogdoches, Texas

Fox SR (1981) John Muir and his legacy: the American conservation movement. Little, Brown, Boston

Freyfogle ET (2000) A Sand County Almanac at 50: Leopold in the new century. Environ Law Report 30:10058–10068

Freyfogle ET (2003) The land we share: private property and the common good. Island Press, Washington

Freyfogle ET (2006) Why conservation is failing and how it can regain ground. Yale University Press, New Haven

Freyfogle ET (2009) Land ethic. In: Callicott JB, Frodeman R (eds) Encyclopedia of environmental ethics and philosophy, vol 2. Macmillan Reference USA, Detroit, pp 21–26

Freyfogle ET (2017a) A good that transcends: how U.S. culture undermines environmental reform. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

Freyfogle ET (2017b) Leopold’s last talk. In: A good that transcends: how U.S. culture undermines environmental reform. University of Chicago Press, pp 8–35

Fritzell PA ([1976] 1987) The conflicts of ecological conscience. In: Callicott JB (ed) Companion to a sand county almanac : interpretive and critical essays. University of Wisconsin Press, Madison, pp 128–153

Gibbons B (1981) The natural world of Aldo Leopold. National Geographic 160:682–708

Gilbert J (2015) Planning democracy: agrarian intellectuals and the intended new deal. Yale University Press, New Haven

Gilbert J, Baker E (1997) Wisconsin economists and new deal agricultural policy: the legacy of progressive professors. Wis Mag Hist 80:280–312

Glotfelty C, Fromm H (eds) (1996) The ecocriticism reader: landmarks in literary ecology. University of Georgia Press, Athens

Gottlieb R (2005) Forcing the spring: the transformation of the American environmental movement, revised and updated edn. Island Press, Washington

Gould SJ (1996) The mismeasure of man, revised and expanded edn. Norton, New York

Graebner W (1991) The age of doubt: American thought and culture in the 1940s. Twayne Publishers, Boston

Greenwood DA (2017) Making restoration history: reconsidering Aldo Leopold’s Arboretum dedication speeches. Restor Ecol 25:681–688. https://doi.org/10.1111/rec.12547

Guha R (1989) Radical American environmentalism and wilderness perservation: a third world critique. Environ Ethics 11:71–83

Hadley AT (1913) Some influences in modern philosophic thought. Yale University Press, New Haven

Haswell SO, Alanen AR (1995) Colonizing the cutover: Wisconsin’s progressive-era experiments in rural planning. Landsc J 14:171–187. https://doi.org/10.3368/lj.14.2.171

Hays SP (1959) Conservation and the gospel of efficiency: the progressive conservation movement, 1890–1920. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

Hays SP (1987) Beauty, health, and permanence: environmental politics in the United States, 1955–1985. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

Helms D (1985) The Civilian Conservation Corps: demonstrating the value of soil conservation. J Soil Water Conserv 40:184–188

Henderson HO, Hembre IO (1955) The coon valley watershed project—a pioneer venture in good land use. J Soil Water Conserv 10:180–184

Hines TS (1967) Echoes from ‘Zenith:’ reactions of American businessmen to babbitt. Bus Hist Rev 41:123–140

Huggard CJ (2001) America’s first wilderness area: Aldo Leopold, the Forest Service, and the Gila of New Mexico, 1924–1980. In: Huggard CJ, Gómez AR (eds) Forests under fire: a century of ecosystem mismanagement in the Southwest. University of Arizona Press, Tucson, pp 133–180

Huntington E (1931) The Matamek conference on biological cycles, 1931. Science 74:229–235

Jarrett H (1958) Perspectives on conservation: essays on America’s natural resources. Johns Hopkins Press for Resources for the Future, Baltimore

Jones SD (2017) Population cycles, disease, and networks of ecological knowledge. J Hist Biol 50:357–391. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10739-016-9441-z

Jordan WR III, Lubick GM (2011) Making nature whole: a history of ecological restoration. Island Press, Washington

Joyner NC (1980) What ever happened to Tristram? Colby Q 16:118–122

Kawall J (2015) A history of environmental ethics. In: Gardiner SM, Thompson A (eds) The Oxford handbook of environmental ethics. Oxford University Press, Oxford

Kersten AE (2007) A. Philip Randolph: a life in the Vanguard. Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, Lanham

Kimmerer RW (2000) Native knowledge for native ecosystems. J For 98:4–9. https://doi.org/10.1093/jof/98.8.4

Knight RL (1996) Aldo Leopold, the land ethic, and ecosystem management. J Wildl Manag 60:471–474

Knight RL (2002) Aldo Leopold: blending conversations about public and private lands. In: Knight RL, Riedel S (eds) Aldo Leopold and the ecological conscience. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 34–45

Knight RL (2009) The wisdom of the Sierra Madre: Aldo Leopold, the Apaches, and the land ethic. In: López-Hoffman L, McGovern ED, Varady RG, Flessa KW (eds) Conservation of shared environments: learning from the United States and Mexico. University of Arizona Press, Tucson

Knight RL, Riedel S (eds) (2002) Aldo Leopold and the ecological conscience. Oxford University Press, New York

Kohler RE (2011) Paul Errington, Aldo Leopold, and wildlife ecology: residential science. Hist Stud Nat Sci 41:216–254

Laubach SA (2014) Living a land ethic: a history of cooperative conservation on the Leopold memorial reserve. The University of Wisconsin Press, Madison, Wisconsin

Lazier B (2011) Earthrise; or, the globalization of the world picture. Am Hist Rev 116:602–630. https://doi.org/10.1086/ahr.116.3.602

Leopold A (1908) Lecture notes for course #20 forest management by H.H. Chapman. Aldo Leopold Archives 10-12 Box 2 folder 9

Leopold A ([1909] 2013) Letter to Clara Leopold. In: Meine C (ed) A Sand County Almanac & other writings on ecology and conservation. The Library of America, New York, pp 740–742

Leopold A (1921a) A plea for recognition of artificial works in forest erosion control policy. J For 19:267–273

Leopold A (1921b) The wilderness and its place in forest recreational policy. J For 19:718–721

Leopold A (1931) Report on a game survey of the North Central States. Democrat Press for Sporting Arms and Ammunitions Manufacturers’ Institute, Madison, Wisconsin

Leopold A (1936a) Deer and Dauerwald in Germany—I. History. J For 34:366–375

Leopold A (1936b) Deer and Dauerwald in Germany—II. Ecology and policy. J For 34:460–466

Leopold A (1936c) Farm game management in Silesia American wildlife 25(67–68):74–76

Leopold A (1937b) The thick-billed parrot in Chihuahua. Condor 39:74–75

Leopold A (1940) History of the Riley game cooperative, 1931–1939. J Wildl Manag 4:291–302

Leopold A (1945) The distribution of Wisconsin Hares. Trans Wis Acad Sci Arts Lett 37:1–14

Leopold A (1946a) Conservation. Aldo Leopold Archives 10-1 Box 1 folder 14, 510

Leopold A (1946b) Erosion as a menace to the social and economic future of the Southwest. J For 44:627–633

Leopold A (1946c) Racial wisdom and conservation. J Hered 37:275–279

Leopold A (1947) Introduction to round-table discussion on game and fur population mechanisms. Aldo Leopold Archives 10-2 Box 2 folder 10, 953–959

Leopold A (1949) A sand county almanac and sketches here and there. Oxford University Press, New York

Leopold A (1953) Round river: from the journals of Aldo Leopold. Oxford University Press, New York

Leopold LB (1987) Foreword. In: Aldo Leopold: The Professor. Rusty Rock Press, Madison, Wisconsin, p viii

Leopold A (1991) The river of the mother of god and other essays. University of Wisconsin Press, Madison

Leopold A (1995) Aldo Leopold’s Southwest. University of New Mexico Press, Albuquerque

Leopold A (1999) For the health of the land: previously unpublished essays and other writings. Island Press, Washington, DC

Leopold AC (2004) Living with the land ethic bioscience 54:149–154

Leopold A (2013) A sand county almanac and other writings on ecology and conservation. Library of America, New York

Leopold EB (2016) Stories from the Leopold shack: sand county revisited. Oxford University Press, Oxford

Leopold A (2018) Aldo Leopold on forestry and conservation: toward a durable scale of values. Society of American Foresters, Bethesda, MD

Leopold A ([1920] 1991) The forestry of the prophets. In: Flader SL, Callicott JB (eds) The river of the mother of god and other essays. University of Wisconsin Press, Madison, Wisconsin. pp 71–77

Leopold A ([1921] 1991) The wilderness and its place in forest recreational policy. In: Flader SL, Callicott JB (eds) The river of the mother of god and other essays. The University of Wisconsin Press, Madison, Wisconsin. pp 78–81

Leopold A ([1923] 1979) Some fundamentals of conservation in the southwest. Environ Ethics 1:131–141

Leopold A ([1923] 1991a) A criticism of the booster spirit. In: Flader SL, Callicott JB (eds) The river of the mother of god and other essays. University of Wisconsin Press, Madison, Wisconsin. pp 98–105

Leopold A ([1923] 1991b) Some fundamentals of conservation in the Southwest. In: Flader SL, Callicott JB (eds) The river of the mother of god and other essays. University of Wisconsin Press, Madison. pp 86–97

Leopold A ([1924] 1991a) Grass, brush, timber, and fire in Southern Arizona. In: Flader SL, Callicott JB (eds) The river of the mother of god and other essays. University of Wisconsin Press, Madison, Wisconsin, pp 114–122

Leopold A ([1924] 1991b) Pioneers and gullies. In: Flader SL, Callicott JB (eds) The river of the mother of god and other essays. University of Wisconsin Press, Madison, Wisconsin, pp 106–113

Leopold A ([1924] 1991c) The river of the mother of god. In: Flader SL, Callicott JB (eds) The river of the mother of god and other essays. University of Wisconsin Press, Madison, Wisconsin, pp 123–127

Leopold A ([1925] 1991) Conserving the covered wagon. In: Flader SL, Callicott JB (eds) The river of the mother of god and other essays. University of Wisconsin Press, Madison, pp 128–132

Leopold A ([1932] 1991) Game and wild life conservation. In: Flader SL, Callicott JB (eds) The river of the mother of god and other essays. University of Wisconsin Press, Madison, Wisconsin, pp 164–168

Leopold A ([1933] 1986) Game management. University of Wisconsin Press, Madison

Leopold A ([1933] 1991) The conservation ethic. In: Flader SL, Callicott JB (eds) The river of the mother of god and other essays. University of Wisconsin Press, Madison, pp 181–192

Leopold A ([1934] 1984) What is the University of Wisconsin Arboretum, wild life refuge, and forest experiment preserve? In: Jordan WR, III (ed) Our first 50 years: the University of Wisconsin-Madison Arboretum 1934–1984. University of Wisconsin-Madison Arboretum, Madison, pp 2–5. http://digital.library.wisc.edu/1711.dl/EcoNatRes.ArbFirstYrs

Leopold A ([1934] 1991a) The Arboretum and the University. In: Flader SL, Callicott JB (eds) The river of the mother of god and other essays. University of Wisconsin Press, Madison, pp 209–211

Leopold A ([1934] 1991b) Conservation economics. In: Flader SL, Callicott JB (eds) The river of the mother of god and other essays. University of Wisconsin Press, Madison, pp 193–202

Leopold A ([1934] 1991c) Helping ourselves. In: Flader SL, Callicott JB (eds) The river of the mother of god and other essays. University of Wisconsin Press, Madison, pp 203–208

Leopold A ([1935] 1991a) Coon Valley: an adventure in cooperative conservation. In: Flader SL, Callicott JB (eds) The river of the mother of god and other essays. University of Wisconsin Press, Madison, Wisconsin, pp 218–223

Leopold A ([1935] 1991b) Land pathology. In: Flader SL, Callicott JB (eds) The river of the mother of god and other essays. University of Wisconsin Press, Madison, pp 212–217

Leopold A ([1935] 1991c) Wilderness. In: Flader SL, Callicott JB (eds) The river of the mother of god and other essays. University of Wisconsin Press, Madison, Wisconsin, pp 226–229

Leopold A ([1935] 2013) Why the wilderness society? In: Meine C (ed) A sand county almanac and other writings on ecology and conservation. The Library of America, New York, pp 369–370

Leopold A ([1936] 2013) Naturschutz in Germany. In: Meine C (ed) A sand county almanac and other writings on ecology and conservation. The Library of America, New York, pp 381–393

Leopold A ([1937] 1991) Conservationist in Mexico. In: Flader SL, Callicott JB (eds) The river of the mother of god and other essays. University of Wisconsin Press, Madison, Wisconsin, pp 239–244

Leopold A ([1938] 1991) Engineering and conservation. In: Flader SL, Callicott JB (eds) The river of the mother of god and other essays. University of Wisconsin Press, Madison, pp 249–254

Leopold A ([1939] 1991a) A biotic view of land. In: Flader SL, Callicott JB (eds) The river of the mother of god and other essays. University of Wisconsin Press, Madison, pp 266–273

Leopold A ([1939] 1991b) The farmer as a conservationist. In: Flader SL, Callicott JB (eds) The river of the mother of god and other essays. University of Wisconsin Press, Madison, pp 255–265

Leopold A ([1940] 2013) Letter to Gifford Pinchot, 4 january 1940. In: Meine C (ed) A sand county almanac and other writings on ecology and conservation. The Library of America, New York, pp 814–815

Leopold A ([1941] 1991a) Ecology and politics. In: Flader SL, Callicott JB (eds) The river of the mother of god and other essays. University of Wisconsin Press, Madison, Wisconsin, pp 281–286

Leopold A ([1941] 1991b) Wilderness as a land laboratory. In: Flader SL, Callicott JB (eds) The river of the mother of god and other essays. University of Wisconsin Press, Madison, pp 287–289

Leopold A ([1942] 1991) Land-use and democracy. In: Flader SL, Callicott JB (eds) The river of the mother of god and other essays. University of Wisconsin Press, Madison, Wisconsin, pp 295–300

Leopold A ([1944] 1991) Conservation: in whole or in part? In: Flader SL, Callicott JB (eds) The river of the mother of god and other essays. University of Wisconsin Press, Madison, pp 310–319

Leopold A ([1944] 2013) Post-war prospects. In: Meine C (ed) A sand county almanac and other writings on ecology and conservation. The Library of America, New York, pp 492–495

Leopold A ([1946] 1991) Adventures of a conservation commissioner. In: Flader SL, Callicott JB (eds) The river of the mother of god and other essays. University of Wisconsin Press, Madison, pp 330–335

Leopold A ([1946] 1999) The land-health concept and conservation. In: Callicott JB, Freyfogle ET (eds) For the health of the land: previously unpublished essays and other writings. Island Press, Washington, DC, pp 218–226

Leopold A ([1947] 1987) Foreword. In: Callicott JB (ed) Companion to a sand county almanac: interpretive & critical essays. University of Wisconsin Press, Madison, pp 281–288

Leopold A ([1947] 1991a) The ecological conscience. In: Flader SL, Callicott JB (eds) The river of the mother of god and other essays. University of Wisconsin Press, Madison, Wisconsin, pp 338–346

Leopold A ([1947] 1991b) Wherefore wildlife ecology? In: Flader SL, Callicott JB (eds) The river of the mother of god and other essays. The University of Wisconsin Press, Madison, pp 336–337

Leopold A. (c.1934). The farm foundation and land conservation. Aldo Leopold Archives 10-2 Box 4 folder 2, 3–8

Leopold A, Jones SE (1947) A phenological record for Sauk and Dane Counties, Wisconsin, 1935–1945. Ecol Monogr 17:81–122. https://doi.org/10.2307/1948614 http://www.jstor.org/stable/1948614

Leopold A, Sperry TM, Feeney WS, Catenhusen JA (1943) Population turnover on a wisconsin pheasant refuge. J Wildl Manag 7:383–394. https://doi.org/10.2307/3796179

Leopold A, Sowls LK, Spencer DL (1947) A survey of over-populated deer ranges in the United States. J Wildl Manag 11:162–177. https://doi.org/10.2307/3795561

Leopold A (1948) Why and how research? Delivered march 8 at thirteenth North American wildlife conference, St. Louis, Missouri. Aldo Leopold Archives 10-2 Box 5 folder 15, 925–928

Lewis S (1922) Babbitt. Harcourt, Brace & Co., New York. https://www.gutenberg.org/ebooks/1156

Liegel K (1982) The pre-European settlement vegetation of the Aldo Leopold memorial reserve transactions of the Wisconsin Academy of Sciences. Arts and Letters 70:13–26

Liegel K (1988) Land use and vegetational change on the Aldo Leopold memorial reserve transactions of the Wisconsin Academy of Sciences. Arts and Letters 76:47–68

Lin QF (2014) Aldo Leopold’s unrealized proposals to rethink economics. Ecol Econ 108:104–114. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.ecolecon.2014.10.018

Lin QF, Fyles JW (2015) Following in Aldo Leopold’s footsteps: humans-in-ecosystem and implications for ecosystem health. In: Brown P, Timmerman P (eds) Ecological economics for the anthropocene: an emerging paradigm. Columbia University Press, New York, pp 208–232. https://doi.org/10.7312/brow17342-008

Lindeman RL (1942) The trophic-dynamic aspect of ecology. Ecology 23:399–417. https://doi.org/10.2307/1930126

Lorbiecki M (2016) A fierce green fire: Aldo Leopold’s life and legacy. Oxford University Press, New York

Love GA (1993) Babbitt: an American life. Twayne Publishers, New York

Lovelock J (1979) Gaia, a new look at life on earth. Oxford University Press, Oxford, New York

Low M (2011) The Lawrenceville letters: tracking the origins of Aldo Leopold’s environmental education. Interdiscip Stud Lit Environ 18:801–819. https://doi.org/10.1093/isle/isr109

MacCleery D (2008) Re-inventing the United States forest service: evolution of national forests from custodial management, to production forestry, to ecosystem management. In: Durst P, Brown C, Broadhead J, Suzuki R, Leslie R, Inoguchi A (eds) Re-inventing forestry agencies: experiences of institutional restructuring in Asia and the Pacific. UN FAO, Regional Office for Asia and the Pacific, Bangkok, Thailand, pp 45–77. http://www.fao.org/docrep/010/ai412e/ai412e00.htm

Maher NM (2008) Nature’s new deal: the civilian conservation corps and the roots of the American environmental movement. Oxford University Press, Oxford, New York

St. Maurice H (2014) On a rhetorical technique in Leopold’s the Land ethic:“that imperial first word”. SAGE Open 4:1–6. https://doi.org/10.1177/2158244014560546

McCabe RA (1978) The stoughton faville prairie preserve: some historical aspects. Trans Wisconsin Acad Sci Arts Lett 66:25–49

McCabe RA (1987) Aldo Leopold: the professor. Rusty Rock Press, Madison, WI

McHarg IL (1969) Design with nature. Natural History Press for the American Museum of Natural History, Garden City, N.Y.

McNeill JR (2010) The state of the field of environmental history. Annu Rev Environ Resour 35:345–374. https://doi.org/10.1146/annurev-environ-040609-105431

Meadows DH, Meadows DL, Randers J, Behrens WW (1972) The limits to growth: a report for the club of Rome’s project on the predicament of mankind. Universe Books, New York

Meine C (1987) Aldo Leopold and the biotic view of history. Wisconsin Acad Rev Aldo Leopold Centen 1887–1987 34:24–26. http://digicoll.library.wisc.edu/cgi-bin/WI/WI-idx?type=article&did=WI.v34i1.CMeine&id=WI.v34i1&isize=L

Meine C (2004) Correction lines: essays on land, leopold, and conservation. Island Press, Washington, DC

Meine C (2009a) Conservation. In: Callicott JB, Frodeman R (eds) Encyclopedia of environmental ethics and philosophy, vol 1. Macmillan reference USA, Detroit, MI, pp 169–175. https://link.gale.com/apps/doc/CX3234100071/GVRL?u=nantecun&sid=GVRL&xid=e9cc9e34

Meine C (2009b) Early wolf research and conservation in the Great Lakes region. In: Wydeven AP, Van Deelen TR, Heske EJ (eds) Recovery of gray wolves in the Great Lakes region of the United States: an endangered species success story. Springer New York, New York, NY, pp 1–13. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-0-387-85952-1_1

Meine C (2010) Aldo Leopold: his life and work. University of Wisconsin Press, Madison

Meine C (2013) Aldo Leopold: connecting conservation science, ethics, policy, and practice. In: Rozzi R, Pickett STA, Palmer C, Armesto JJ, Callicott BJ (eds) Linking ecology and ethics for a changing world: values, philosophy, and action. Springer Netherlands, Dordrecht, pp 173–184. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-7470-4_14

Meine C (2017a) Aldo Leopold. Oxford bibliographies—ecology. https://doi.org/10.1093/OBO/9780199830060-0037

Meine C (2017b) Restoration and “novel ecosystems”: priority or paradox? Ann Mo Bot Gard 102(2):217–226

Meine C, Knight RL (eds) (1999) The essential Aldo Leopold: quotations and commentaries. University of Wisconsin Press, Madison

Merchant C (2003) Shades of darkness: race and environmental history. Environ Hist 8:380–394 https://doi.org/10.2307/3986200

Miller C (2001) Gifford pinchot and the making of modern environmentalism. Island Press, Washington, DC

Millstein RL (2015) Re-examining the darwinian basis for Aldo Leopold’s land ethic ethics. Pol Environ 18:301–317. https://doi.org/10.1080/21550085.2015.1111617

Millstein RL (2018a) Debunking myths about Aldo Leopold’s land ethic. Biol Cons 217:391–396. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.biocon.2017.11.027

Millstein RL (2018b) Is Aldo Leopold’s “land community” an individual? In: Bueno O, Chen R-L, Fagan MB (eds) Individuation, process, and scientific practices. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 279–302. https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780190636814.003.0013

Millstein RL (2018c) Understanding Leopold’s concept of “interdependence” for environmental ethics and conservation biology. Philos Sci 85:1127–1139. https://doi.org/10.1086/699721

Minteer BA (2006) The landscape of reform: civic pragmatism and environmental thought in America. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

Mitman G (2005) In search of health: landscape and disease in American environmental history. Environ Hist 10:184–210. https://www.jstor.org/stable/3986112

Naess A (1973) The shallow and the deep, long-range ecology movement: a summary. Inquiry 16:95–100

Nash R (1987) Aldo Leopold’s intellectual heritage. In: Callicott JB (ed) Companion to a sand county almanac : interpretive and critical essays. University of Wisconsin Press, Madison, Wisconsin, pp 63–88

Nash R ([1967] 2014) Wilderness and the American mind, 5th edn. Yale University Press, New Haven, CT

Nelson MP (1996) Holists and fascists and paper tigers…Oh my! Ethics Environ 1:103–117. https://doi.org/10.2307/27766017

Norgaard RB (1989) The case for methodological pluralism. Ecol Econ 1:37–57. https://doi.org/10.1016/0921-8009(89)90023-2

Norlock KJ (2011) Building receptivity: Leopold’s land ethic and critical feminist interpretation. Journal for the study of religion. Nat Cult 5:491–509. https://doi.org/10.1558/jsrnc.v5i4.491

Norton BG (1988) The constancy of Leopold’s land ethic conservation. Biology 2:93–102

Norton BG (2005) Sustainability : A philosophy of adaptive ecosystem management. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

Norton BG (2011) What Leopold learned from Darwin and Hadley: comment on callicott et al. Environ Values 20:7–16

O’Shea EA (2018) Distinguishing harms to derive commitments: Karen Warren and Aldo Leopold on ecofeminism and domination. Standard Theses, 166, https://scarab.bates.edu/envr_studies_theses/166

Omi M, Winant H (2015) Racial formation in the United States, 3rd edn. Routledge/Taylor & Francis Group, New York

Orr DW (1999) What is education for? In: Meine C, Knight RL (eds) The essential Aldo Leopold: quotations and commentaries. University of Wisconsin Press, Madison, pp 255–257

Osborn F (1948) Our plundered planet. Little, Brown and Co., Boston

Ouderkirk W, Hill J (eds) (2002) Land, value, community: callicott and environmental philosophy. State University of New York Press, Albany

Ouspensky PD (1920) Tertium organum. Manas Press, Rochester

Oxford English Dictionary Online (2019) Babbitt, n.2. https://www.oed.com/view/Entry/14196 . Accessed 13 February 2019

Özdağ U (2017) Edebiyat ve Toprak Etiği: Amerikan Doğa Yazınında Leopold’cu Düşünce (Literature

Palmer MA, Zedler JB, Falk DA (2016) Ecological theory and restoration ecology. In: Palmer MA, Zedler JB, Falk DA (eds) Foundations of restoration ecology. Island Press, Washington, DC, pp 3–26

Pister EP (1987) A Pilgrim’s progress from group A to group B. In: Callicott JB (ed) Companion to a sand county almanac: interpretive and critical essays. University of Wisconsin Press, Madison, pp 221–232

Pister EP (2002) The A-B dichotomy and the future. In: Knight RL, Riedel S (eds) Aldo Leopold and the ecological conscience. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 158–167

Poole R (2008) Earthrise: how man first saw the Earth. Yale University Press, New Haven, Connecticut

Potter VR (1988) Global bioethics: building on the Leopold legacy. Michigan State University Press, East Lansing

Powell MA (2016) Vanishing America: species extinction, racial peril, and the origins of conservation. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts

Proctor JD (1996) Will the real land ethic please stand up? J Forest 94:39–43

Pryor A (2011) ‘Thinking like a mystic’: the unacknowledged legacy of PD ouspenksy’s Tertium Organum on the development of Leopold’s ‘Thinking like a mountain’. J Study Relig Nat Cult 5:465–490. https://doi.org/10.1558/jsrnc.v5i4.465

Radcliffe SJ (2000) A professional code of ethics for the 21st century: the ethics committee’s proposal. J For 98:16–21

Rees WE (1992) Ecological footprints and appropriated carrying capacity: what urban economics leaves out. Environ Urban 4:121–130

Regan T (1983) The case for animal rights. University of California Press, Berkeley

Ribbens D (1987a) An introduction to the 1947 foreword [to great possessions ]. In: Callicott JB (ed) Companion to a sand county almanac : interpretive & critical essays. University of Wisconsin Press, Madison, Wisconsin, pp 277–280

Ribbens D (1987b) The making of a Sand County Almanac . In: Callicott JB (ed) Companion to a sand county almanac : interpretive and critical essays. University of Wisconsin Press, Madison, pp 91–109

Robertson T (2012) The malthusian moment: global population growth and the birth of American environmentalism. Rutgers University Press, New Brunswick, New Jersey

Robinson EA (1927) Tristram. Macmillan Company, New York

Rogers TB (2003) Revisioning our views of “nature” through an examination of Aldo Leopold’s a sand county almanac. Interdisc Stud Lit Environ 10:47–73

Rolston H (1975) Is there an ecological ethic? Ethics 85:93–109. www.jstor.org/stable/2379925

Rome A (2013) The genius of earth day: how a 1970 teach-in unexpectedly made the first green generation. Hill and Wang, New York

Salwén H (2014) The land ethic and the significance of the fascist objection ethics. Policy Environ 17:192–207. https://doi.org/10.1080/21550085.2014.926084

Sandlos J (2013) Nature’s nations: the shared conservation history of Canada and the USA. Int J Environ Stud 70:358–371. https://doi.org/10.1080/00207233.2013.800356

Savoy W (1949) Alien land. E. P, Dutton, New York

Savoy LE (2015) Trace: memory, history, race, and the American landscape. Counterpoint, Berkeley, California

Sayre NF (2008) The genesis, history, and limits of carrying capacity. Ann Assoc Am Geogr 98:120–134. https://doi.org/10.1080/00045600701734356

Schabel HG (2001) Deer and dauerwald in Germany: any progress? Wildl Soc Bull 29:888–898

Schumacher EF (1973) Small is beautiful: economics as if people mattered. Harper & Row, New York

Shepard P, McKinley D (1969) The subversive science: essays toward an ecology of man. Houghton Mifflin, Boston

Sherman SP (1914) Review of some influences in modern philosophic thought by A. T. Hadley, 1913. Yale Rev 3:383–385

Shilling D (2009) Aldo Leopold listens to the Southwest. J Southwest 51:317–350. https://doi.org/10.2307/40599694 http://www.jstor.org/stable/40599694

Silbernagel R, Silbernagel J (2003) Tracking Aldo Leopold through riley’s farmland: remembering the Riley game cooperative. Wis Mag Hist 86:34–45

Smedley A, Smedley BD (2012) Race in North America: origin and evolution of a worldview, 4th edn. Westview Press, Boulder CO

Smyth AV (1995) Foresters and the land: the evolution of SAF’s land ethic. J For 93:222–225

Stark J (1995) The wisconsin idea: the University’s service to the State. 1995–1996 Wisconsin blue book. Wisconsin Legislative Reference Bureau, Madison, pp 101–179

Stegner W (1987) The legacy of Aldo Leopold. In: Callicott JB (ed) Companion to a sand county almanac : interpretive and critical essays. University of Wisconsin Press, Madison, pp 233–245

Stephens PHG (2018) Norton versus callicott on interpreting Aldo Leopold: a jamesian view. In: Minteer BA (ed) Sarkar S. The work of Bryan Norton. Springer International Publishing, A Sustainable Philosophy, pp 25–133

Sutter P (2002) Driven wild: how the fight against automobiles launched the modern wilderness movement. University of Washington Press, Seattle

Sylvan R ([1973] 2001) Is there a need for a new, an environmental, ethic? In: Zimmerman ME (ed) Environmental philosophy: from animal rights to radical ecology, 3rd edn. Prentice Hall, Upper Saddle River, NJ, pp 17–25

Tallmadge J (1987) Anatomy of a classic. In: Callicott JB (ed) Companion to a sand county almanac : interpretive and critical essays. University of Wisconsin Press, Madison, pp 110–127

Tanner T (ed) (1987) Aldo Leopold: the man and his legacy. Soil Conservation Society of America, Ankeny, Iowa

Taylor WP (1935) Significance of the biotic community in ecological studies. Q Rev Biol 10:291–307

Temple SA (1999) Building the foundations of wildlife conservation. In: Meine C, Knight RL (eds) The essential Aldo Leopold: quotations and commentaries. University of Wisconsin Press, Madison, pp 45–49

Temple SA (2017) Aldo Leopold: the radio transcripts. Wisconsin Public Radio, University of the Air, aired April 23, 4:00 pm. https://www.wpr.org/shows/aldo-leopold-radio-transcripts

Thomas WL (ed) (1956) Man’s role in changing the face of the earth. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

Thomas JW (2002) What would Aldo have done? A personal story. In: Knight RL, Riedel S (eds) Aldo Leopold and the ecological conscience. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 168–177

Udall S (1963) The quiet crisis. Holt, Rinehart and Winston, New York

Van Auken P (2020) Toward fusion of two lines of thought: creating convergence between Aldo Leopold and sociology through the community concept. Socio-Ecol Pract Res. https://doi.org/10.1007/s42532-020-00042-7

Van Horn G (2011) Fire on the mountain: ecology gets its narrative totem. J Study Relig Nat Cult 5:437–464

Vest JHC (1987) The philosophical significance of wilderness solitude. Environ Ethics 9:303–330

Vogt W (1948) Road to survival. W. Sloane Associates, New York

Wackernagel M, Rees WE (1996) Our ecological footprint: reducing human impact on the earth. New Society Publishers, Gabriola Island, BC

Wade D. (1944). Letter to Aldo Leopold, 30 September 1944. Aldo Leopold Archives 10-8 box 1 folder 3, 466–468

Waller DM, Flader SL (2010) Leopold’s legacy: an ecology of place. In: Billick I, Price MV (eds) The ecology of place: contributions of place-based research to ecological understanding. University of Chicago Press, Chicago, pp 40–62

Waller DM, Rooney TP (2008) The vanishing present: Wisconsin’s changing lands, waters, and wildlife. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

Warren K (2000) Ecofeminist philosophy: a western perspective on what it is and why it matters. Rowman & Littlefield, Lanham, Md

Warren JL (2008) Science, recreation, and Leopold’s quest for a durable scale. In: Nelson MP, Callicott JB (eds) The wilderness debate rages on: continuing the great new wilderness debate. University of Georgia Press, Athens, pp 97–118

Warren JL (2016) Aldo Leopold’s odyssey, 10th anniversary edn. Island Press, Washington

Welchman J (2009) Hume, callicott, and the land ethic: prospects and problems. J Value Inq 43:201–220. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10790-009-9150-3

Westra L (1994) An environmental proposal for ethics: the principle of integrity. Studies in social and political philosophy. Rowman & Littlefield, Lanham, Md

White L, Jr. (1967) The historical roots of our ecologic crisis science 155:1203–1207. http://www.jstor.org/stable/1720120

Whyte KP (2015) How similar are indigenous North American and Leopoldian environmental ethics? Available at http://ssrn.com/abstract=2022038 or http://dx.doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.2022038

Wildermuth AJ (2002) Eco-pragmatism and ecology: what’s Leopold got to do with it. Minnesota Law Rev 87:1145–1172

Willard BE (2007) Rhetorical landscapes as epistemic: revisiting Aldo Leopold’s a sand county almanac environmental. Communication 1:218–235. https://doi.org/10.1080/17524030701642785

Worster D (1993) The wealth of nature: environmental history and the ecological imagination. Oxford University Press, New York

Worster D (1994a) Nature’s economy: a history of ecological ideas, 2nd edn. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK

Worster D (1994b) An unsettled country: changing landscapes of the American West. University of New Mexico Press, Albuquerque

Worster D (1999) Leopold and the changing landscape of history. In: Meine C, Knight RL (eds) The essential Aldo Leopold: quotations and commentaries. University of Wisconsin Press, Madison, pp 237–239

Yale School of Forestry & Environmental Studies (2020) Yale F&ES to become the Yale school of the environment. https://environment.yale.edu/news/article/school-of-forestry-and-environmental-studies-to-become-yale-school-of-the-environment

Ybarra PS (2016) Writing the goodlife: Mexican American literature and the environment. The University of Arizona Press, Tucson

Download references

Acknowledgements

I thank Wei-Ning Xiang, the editor-in-chief of Socio-Ecological Practice Research , for giving me the opportunity to write this review, Curt Meine for his helpful comments, William Rees and Richard Norgaard for permission to share their experience with Aldo Leopold, and Vincent Wong at the Nanyang Technological University Library for assistance with the cited reference search of ASCA .

Author information

Authors and affiliations.

History Programme, School of Humanities, Nanyang Technological University, 48 Nanyang Avenue, SHHK-05-16, Singapore, 639818, Singapore

Lin Qi Feng

You can also search for this author in PubMed   Google Scholar

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Lin Qi Feng .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Lin, Q.F. Aldo Leopold’s life–work and the scholarship it inspired. Socio Ecol Pract Res 2 , 3–30 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s42532-020-00043-6

Download citation

Received : 03 January 2020

Accepted : 20 February 2020

Published : 26 March 2020

Issue Date : March 2020

DOI : https://doi.org/10.1007/s42532-020-00043-6

Share this article

Anyone you share the following link with will be able to read this content:

Sorry, a shareable link is not currently available for this article.

Provided by the Springer Nature SharedIt content-sharing initiative

  • Aldo Leopold
  • A Sand County Almanac
  • Conservation
  • Environmental history
  • Environmental ethics
  • Find a journal
  • Publish with us
  • Track your research
  • DOI: 10.5822/978-1-61091-491-8_12
  • Corpus ID: 38454223

The Land Ethic

  • Published 2014

72 Citations

Bridging the interdisciplinary divide: co-advancing the pedagogy of environmental justice through a digital commons initiative.

  • Highly Influenced

The Moral Values of Pain and Pleasure: A Critique of the Hedonic Definitions

Nature’s economy and news ecology, green consumption values in mobile apps, activism and neoliberalism: two sides of geoengineering discourse, beyond science and technology: the need to incorporate environmental ethics to solve environmental problems, ecological aesthetics: design thinking to landscape beauty with healthy ecology, rights-based approach: the hub of sustainable development, community action: value or instrument an ethics and planning critical review, god, the bible and the environment. an historical excursus on the relationship between christian religion and ecology, one reference, related papers.

Showing 1 through 3 of 0 Related Papers

Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.

To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to  upgrade your browser .

Enter the email address you signed up with and we'll email you a reset link.

  • We're Hiring!
  • Help Center

Beyond the Land Ethic: More Essays in Environmental Philosophy, Edited by J. Baird Callicott, State University of New York Press, Albany, 1999. ISBN 0-7914-4084-2; 427 pp

Profile image of David Rapport

2001, Ecological Economics

Related Papers

Geoffrey B Frasz

research papers on land ethic

Nicole Note

Philosophy in Review

Philip Rose

Between the Species: An Online Journal for the Study of Philosophy and Animals

Roger J H King

Stephen Quilley

Albert Spencer

This article surveys recent attempts to articulate the latent environmental philosophy of Josiah Royce (Selk; Oppenheim; Price; Bell; Minteer; Brunson) and to assess the merits and flaws of these attempts. It will then orient Royce\u27s latent environmental philosophy within the context of contemporary methodologies of environmental ethics in the hopes of demonstrating Royce\u27s relevance and potential to these engagements of current ecological crises. It will conclude by articulating a unique perspective of loyalty to nature founded on a Roycean appeal to moral perfectionism, his response to the egoism of Friedrich Nietzsche, and a blending of the sources presented at the outset. As shall be demonstrated, loyalty to nature provides a novel pragmatic alternative to the anthropocentric-biocentric axiology and a richer, more comprehensive view of humanity\u27s relationship to fellow natural beings, the land, the planet, and nature itself

Isabel Santos

Philip Cafaro

agus wiyono

Bryan Bannon

"From Mastery to Mystery is an original and provocative contribution to the burgeoning field of ecophenomenology. Informed by current debates in environmental philosophy, Bannon critiques the conception of nature as “substance” that he finds tacitly assumed by the major environmental theorists. Instead, this book reconsiders the basic goals of an environmental ethic by questioning the most basic presupposition that most environmentalists accept: that nature is in need of preservation. Beginning with Bruno Latour’s idea that continuing to speak of nature in the way we popularly conceive of it is ethically and politically disastrous, this book describes a way in which the concept of nature can retain its importance in our discussion of the contemporary state of the environment. Based upon insights from the phenomenological tradition, specifically the work of Martin Heidegger and Maurice Merleau-Ponty, the concept of nature developed in the book preserves the best antihumanistic intuitions of environmentalists without relying on either a reductionistic understanding of nature and the sciences or dualistic metaphysical constructions."

Loading Preview

Sorry, preview is currently unavailable. You can download the paper by clicking the button above.

RELATED PAPERS

Environmental Values

Alison Stone

Andrew Brennan

A World not Made for Us: Topics in Critical Environmental Philosophy

Keith R Peterson

vijay srinath kanchi

Brian G. Henning

Ashley Dodsworth

Biodiversity and Conservation

Piers Stephens

Leslie Ryan

Journal of Applied Philosophy

in Facts and Values. The Ethics and Metaphysics of Normativity, eds. Giancarlo Marchetti, Sarin Marchetti, New York – London, Routledge

Piergiorgio Donatelli

jozef keulartz

Educating for Environmental Awareness

Dermot Moran

The Nature Essay

Simone Schröder

Gavin Van Horn

Olivia Bina

abdelmohsen .ibrahim

Oxford Handbooks Online

Benjamin Hale

Southern Journal of Philosophy

Charles Starkey

Ethics and the Environment

Bartlomiej Lenart

Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics

Henry Dicks

Environmental Ethics

Ned Hettinger

RELATED TOPICS

  •   We're Hiring!
  •   Help Center
  • Find new research papers in:
  • Health Sciences
  • Earth Sciences
  • Cognitive Science
  • Mathematics
  • Computer Science
  • Academia ©2024

U.S. flag

An official website of the United States government

The .gov means it’s official. Federal government websites often end in .gov or .mil. Before sharing sensitive information, make sure you’re on a federal government site.

The site is secure. The https:// ensures that you are connecting to the official website and that any information you provide is encrypted and transmitted securely.

  • Publications
  • Account settings

Preview improvements coming to the PMC website in October 2024. Learn More or Try it out now .

  • Advanced Search
  • Journal List
  • Ann Med Surg (Lond)
  • v.86(5); 2024 May
  • PMC11060189

Logo of amsu

Ethics in scientific research: a lens into its importance, history, and future

Associated data.

Not applicable.

Introduction

Ethics are a guiding principle that shapes the conduct of researchers. It influences both the process of discovery and the implications and applications of scientific findings 1 . Ethical considerations in research include, but are not limited to, the management of data, the responsible use of resources, respect for human rights, the treatment of human and animal subjects, social responsibility, honesty, integrity, and the dissemination of research findings 1 . At its core, ethics in scientific research aims to ensure that the pursuit of knowledge does not come at the expense of societal or individual well-being. It fosters an environment where scientific inquiry can thrive responsibly 1 .

The need to understand and uphold ethics in scientific research is pertinent in today’s scientific community. First, the rapid advancement of technology and science raises ethical questions in fields like biotechnology, biomedical science, genetics, and artificial intelligence. These advancements raise questions about privacy, consent, and the potential long-term impacts on society and its environment 2 . Furthermore, the rise in public perception and scrutiny of scientific practices, fueled by a more informed and connected populace, demands greater transparency and ethical accountability from researchers and institutions.

This commentary seeks to bring to light the need and benefits associated with ethical adherence. The central theme of this paper highlights how upholding ethics in scientific research is a cornerstone for progress. It buttresses the fact that ethics in scientific research is vital for maintaining the trust of the public, ensuring the safety of participants, and legitimizing scientific findings.

Historical perspective

Ethics in research is significantly shaped by past experiences where a lack of ethical consideration led to negative consequences. One of the most striking examples of ethical misconduct is the Tuskegee Syphilis Study 3 conducted between 1932 and 1972 by the U.S. Public Health Service. In this study, African American men in Alabama were used as subjects to study the natural progression of untreated syphilis. They were not informed of their condition and were denied effective treatment, even after penicillin became available as a cure in the 1940s 3 .

From an ethical lens today, this is a gross violation of informed consent and an exploitation of a vulnerable population. The public outcry following the revelation of the study’s details led to the establishment of the National Commission for the Protection of Human Subjects of Biomedical and Behavioural Research 4 . This commission eventually produced the Belmont Report in 1979 4 , setting forth principles such as respect for persons, beneficence, and justice, which now underpin ethical research practices 4 .

Another example that significantly impacted ethical regulations was the thalidomide tragedy of the late 1950s and early 1960s 5 . Thalidomide was marketed as a safe sedative for pregnant women to combat morning sickness in Europe. Thalidomide resulted in the birth of approximately ten thousand children with severe deformities due to its teratogenic effects 5 , which were not sufficiently researched prior to the drug’s release. This incident underscored the critical need for comprehensive clinical testing and highlighted the ethical imperative of understanding and communicating potential risks, particularly for vulnerable groups such as pregnant women. In response, drug testing regulations became more rigorous, and the importance of informed consent, especially in clinical trials, was emphasized.

The Stanford Prison Experiment of 1971, led by psychologist Philip Zimbardo is another prime example of ethical oversight leading to harmful consequences 6 . The experiment, which aimed to study the psychological effects of perceived power, resulted in emotional trauma for participants. Underestimating potential psychological harm with no adequate systems to safeguard human participants from harm was a breach of ethics in psychological studies 6 . This case highlighted the necessity for ethical guidelines that prioritize the mental and emotional welfare of participants, especially in psychological research. It led to stricter review processes and the establishment of guidelines to prevent psychological harm in research studies. It influenced the American Psychological Association and other bodies to refine their ethical guidelines, ensuring the protection of participants’ mental and emotional well-being.

Impact on current ethical standards

These historical, ethical oversights have been instrumental in shaping the current landscape of ethical standards in scientific research. The Tuskegee Syphilis Study led to the Belmont Report in 1979, which laid out key ethical principles such as respect for persons, beneficence, and justice. It also prompted the establishment of Institutional Review Boards (IRBs) to oversee research involving human subjects. The thalidomide tragedy catalyzed stricter drug testing regulations and informed consent requirements for clinical trials. The Stanford Prison Experiment influenced the American Psychological Association to refine its ethical guidelines, placing greater emphasis on the welfare and rights of participants.

These historical episodes of ethical oversights have been pivotal in forging the comprehensive ethical frameworks that govern scientific research today. They serve as stark reminders of the potential consequences of ethical neglect and the perpetual need to prioritize the welfare and rights of participants in any research endeavor.

One may ponder on the reason behind the Tuskegee Syphilis Study, where African American men with syphilis were deliberately left untreated. What led scientists to prioritize research outcomes over human well-being? At the time, racial prejudices, lack of understanding of ethical principles in human research, and regulatory oversight made such studies pass. Similarly, the administration of thalidomide to pregnant women initially intended as an antiemetic to alleviate morning sickness, resulted in unforeseen and catastrophic birth defects. This tragedy highlights a critical lapse in the pre-marketing evaluation of drugs’ safety.

Furthermore, the Stanford prison experiment, designed to study the psychological effects of perceived power, spiraled into an ethical nightmare as participants suffered emotional trauma. This begs the question on how these researchers initially justified their methods. From today’s lens of ethics, the studies conducted were a complete breach of misconduct, and I wonder if there were any standards that guided primitive research in science.

Current ethical standards and guidelines in research

Informed consent.

This mandates that participants are fully informed about the nature of the research, including its objectives, procedures, potential risks, and benefits 7 , 8 . They must be given the opportunity to ask questions and must voluntarily agree to participate without coercion 7 , 8 . This ensures respect for individual autonomy and decision-making.

Confidentiality and privacy

Confidentiality is pivotal in research involving human subjects. Participants’ personal information must be protected from unauthorized access or disclosure 7 , 8 . Researchers are obliged to take measures to preserve the anonymity and privacy of participants, which fosters trust and encourages participation in research 7 , 8 .

Non-maleficence and beneficence

These principles revolve around the obligation to avoid harm (non-maleficence) and to maximize possible benefits while minimizing potential harm (beneficence) 7 , 8 . Researchers must ensure that their studies do not pose undue risks to participants and that any potential risks are outweighed by the benefits.

Justice in research ethics refers to the fair selection and treatment of research participants 8 . It ensures that the benefits and burdens of research are distributed equitably among different groups in society, preventing the exploitation of vulnerable populations 8 .

The role of Institutional Review Boards (IRB)

Institutional Review Boards play critical roles in upholding ethical standards in research. An IRB is a committee established by an institution conducting research to review, approve, and monitor research involving human subjects 7 , 8 . Their primary role is to ensure that the rights and welfare of participants are protected.

Review and approval

Before a study commences, the IRB reviews the research proposal to ensure it adheres to ethical guidelines. This includes evaluating the risks and benefits, the process of obtaining informed consent, and measures for maintaining confidentiality 7 , 8 .

Monitoring and compliance

IRB also monitors ongoing research projects to ensure compliance with ethical standards. They may require periodic reports and can conduct audits to ensure ongoing adherence to ethical principles 7 , 8 .

Handling ethical violations

In cases where ethical standards are breached, IRB has the authority to impose sanctions, which can range from requiring modifications to the study to completely halting the research project 7 , 8 .

Other agencies and boards enforcing standards

Beyond IRB, there are other regulatory bodies and agencies at national and international levels that enforce ethical standards in research. These include:

The Office for Human Research Protections (OHRP) in the United States, which oversees compliance with the Federal Policy for the Protection of Human Subjects.

The World Health Organization (WHO) , which provides international ethical guidelines for biomedical research.

The International Committee of Medical Journal Editors (ICMJE) , which sets ethical standards for the publication of biomedical research.

These organizations, along with IRB, form a comprehensive network that ensures the ethical conduct of scientific research. They safeguard the integrity of research using the reflections and lesson learnt from the past.

Benefits of ethical research

Credible and reliable outcomes, why is credibility so crucial in research, and how do ethical practices contribute to it.

Ethical practices such as rigorous peer review, transparent methodology, and adherence to established protocols ensure that research findings are reliable and valid 9 . When studies are conducted ethically, they are less likely to be marred by biases, fabrications, or errors that could compromise credibility. For instance, ethical standards demand accurate data reporting and full disclosure of any potential conflicts of interest 9 , which directly contribute to the integrity and trustworthiness of research findings.

How do ethical practices lead to socially beneficial outcomes?

Ethical research practices often align with broader societal values and needs, leading to outcomes that are not only scientifically significant but also socially beneficial. By respecting principles like justice and beneficence, researchers ensure that their work with human subjects contributes positively to society 7 , 8 . For example, ethical guidelines in medical research emphasize the need to balance scientific advancement with patient welfare, ensuring that new treatments are both effective and safe. This balance is crucial in addressing pressing societal health concerns while safeguarding individual rights and well-being.

Trust between the public and the scientific community

The relationship between the public and the scientific community is heavily reliant on trust, which is fostered through consistent ethical conduct in research. When the public perceives that researchers are committed to ethical standards, it reinforces their confidence in the scientific process and its outcomes. Ethical research practices demonstrate a respect for societal norms and values, reinforcing the perception that science serves the public good.

Case studies

Case study 1: the development and approval of covid-19 vaccines.

The development and approval of COVID-19 vaccines within a short time is a testament to how adherence to ethical research practices can achieve credible and beneficial outcomes. Strict adherence to ethical guidelines, even in the face of a global emergency, ensured that the vaccines were developed swiftly. However, safety standards were compromised to some extent as no animal trials were done before humans. The vaccine development was not transparent to the public, and this fuelled the anti-vaccination crowd in some regions. Ethical compliance, including rigorous testing and transparent reporting, should expedite scientific innovation while maintaining public trust.

Case study 2: The CRISPR babies

What ethical concerns were raised by the creation of the crispr babies, and what were the consequences.

The creation of the first genetically edited babies using CRISPR technology in China raised significant ethical concerns 10 . The lack of transparency, inadequate consent process, and potential risks to the children can be likened to ethical misconduct in genetic engineering research. This case resulted in widespread condemnation from the scientific community and the public, as well as international regulatory frameworks and guidelines for genetic editing research 10 .

Recommendation and conclusion

Continuous education and training.

The scientific community should prioritize ongoing education and training in ethics for researchers at all levels, ensuring awareness and understanding of ethical standards and their importance.

Enhanced dialogue and collaboration

Encourage multidisciplinary collaborations and dialogues between scientists, ethicists, policymakers, and the public to address emerging ethical challenges and develop adaptive guidelines.

Fostering a culture of ethical responsibility

Institutions and researchers should cultivate an environment where ethical considerations are integral to the research process, encouraging transparency, accountability, and social responsibility.

Global standards and cooperation

Work toward establishing and harmonizing international ethical standards and regulatory frameworks, particularly in areas like genetic engineering and AI, where the implications of research are global.

Ethics approval

Ethics approval was not required for this editorial.

Informed consent was not required for this editorial

Sources of funding

No funding was received for this research.

Author contribution

G.D.M. wrote this paper.

Conflicts of interest disclosure

The authors declare no conflicts of interest.

Research registration unique identifying number (UIN)

Goshen David Miteu.

Data availability statement

Provenance and peer review.

Not commissioned, externally peer-reviewed.

Sponsorships or competing interests that may be relevant to content are disclosed at the end of this article.

Published online 21 March 2024

IMAGES

  1. The Land Ethic: What Does It Mean in Practice? 14 CHAPTER

    research papers on land ethic

  2. (PDF) Legislating a Sustainable Land Ethic for New Zealand

    research papers on land ethic

  3. Phil240

    research papers on land ethic

  4. (PDF) The Land Ethic, Moral Development, and Ecological Rationality

    research papers on land ethic

  5. (PDF) Unearthing the Process Roots of Environmental Ethics: Whitehead

    research papers on land ethic

  6. The Land Ethics Reflection Paper .docx

    research papers on land ethic

VIDEO

  1. Young Buffett's Hustle! #warrenbuffett #financialfreedom

  2. Land Back: Indigenous Perspectives

  3. Why Your Work Ethic is Holding You Back: The Shocking Truth About Time and Performance

  4. Screencast: Aldo Leopold's "Land Ethic"

  5. HISTORICAL LAND INJUSTICES

  6. Leopold "The Land Ethic"

COMMENTS

  1. (PDF) Land Ethic? What Land Ethic?

    Just over 60 years ago, Aldo Leopold argued for a 'land ethic,' a self-imposed. limitation on the degree to which a person modifies the landscape, in order to protect. overall ecosystem ...

  2. Aldo Leopold and the Land Ethic

    'The land ethic simply enlarges the boundaries of the community to include soils, waters, plants, and animals, or collectively: the land,' Footnote 2 he wrote, adding that 'a land ethic changes the role of Homo sapiens from conqueror of the land-community to plain member and citizen of it. It implies respect for his fellow-members, and ...

  3. (PDF) The land ethic today

    Academia.edu is a platform for academics to share research papers. The land ethic today ... Press, 1974). 46 Eugene C. Hargrove, Foundations of Environmental Ethics (New York: Prentice Hall, t989). THE LAND ETHIC TODAY 47 David J. Schaeffer, Edwin H. Herricks, and Harold W. Kerster, Ecosystem Health: I. Measuring Ecosystem Health ...

  4. Aldo Leopold and the Land Ethic

    This paper explores the relationship between Leopold's lifelong observations and reflections on the problems of soil erosion and soil productivity and the evolution of his land ethic philosophy. It considers also the role of his thinking about climate change, landscape ecology, and ethics in the shaping of his ideas about public policy.

  5. The Land Ethic and the Earth Ethic(s)

    The land ethic is local in scale. Therefore, an earth ethic is needed. Leopold sketched several in 1923: a three-pronged virtue ethic, a care ethic for posterity, an ethic of respect for the living planet. An individualistic ethic for distant future generations falls afoul of the non-identity paradox. Fiduciary care for global civilization can ...

  6. The Land Ethic: A Critical Account of Its Philosophical and

    In Chapter 1, I provide an analysis of the larger whole, A Sand County Almanac and Sketches Here and There, of which "The Land Ethic" is the crowning part—the capstone essay, the climax, the denouement.The land ethic represents the axiological (ethical and aesthetical) and normative (practical moral) implications of an evolutionary-ecological worldview, which is gradually exposed and ...

  7. [PDF] The Land Ethic

    The Land Ethic. J. B. Callicott. Published 13 December 2007. Environmental Science, Philosophy. The Darwinian roots of the land ethic or all the environmental ethics so far devised. the land ethic. first sketched by Aldo Leopold (I HR 7-194R), is most popular among professional conservationists and least popular among professional philosophers.

  8. (PDF) Land, ethics, justice, and Aldo Leopold

    Academia.edu is a platform for academics to share research papers. Land, ethics, justice, and Aldo Leopold ... The standard interpretation of Aldo Leopold's land ethic is that correct land management is whatever tends to preserve the integrity, stability, and beauty of the biotic community, of which we humans are merely a small part. ...

  9. The Land Ethic

    The holism of the land ethic and its antecedents. The holism of the land ethic and the problem of eco-fascism. Prioritizing the duties generated by membership in multiple communities. The priority (second-order) principles applied to the old-growth forest quandary. The land ethic in the time of a shifting science of ecology.

  10. (PDF) Internalizing Aldo Leopold's Land Ethic: The Communitarian

    This paper, then, is an exploration of Leopold's land ethic and its more accurate application through biocultural stewardship. Keywords: biocultural stewardship, bioculturalism, stewardship, land ethic, Aldo Leopold, environmental ethics, cultural diversity, biodiversity, cultural diversity, culture "

  11. Ethics for Wildlife Conservation: Overcoming the Human-Nature Dualism

    Examples of such holistic approaches are Aldo Leopold's "land ethic" (1970, Callicott 1998) and Rolston's "environmental ethics" (1991). Leopold's essay "The Land Ethic" (1970) is considered by many the foundational work in holistic environmental ethics, although more recent interpretations focus on anthropocentric elements in ...

  12. Aldo Leopold's life-work and the scholarship it inspired

    Since its publication in 1949, Aldo Leopold's A Sand County Almanac, especially "The Land Ethic" essay, has been influential in conservation and environmental circles. In this wide-ranging but limited review, I discussed Leopold's life and work, including the important concepts he had written about, and briefly survey the secondary literature he inspired in the realms of science ...

  13. (PDF) Teaching the Land Ethic

    Abstract. This paper discusses the teaching of the Leopoldian Land Ethic in an environmental ethics class. The Leopoldian Land Ethic is arguably the most fully formulated and developed ...

  14. Land Ethic? What Land Ethic?

    Just over 60 years ago, Aldo Leopold argued for a 'land ethic,' a self-imposed limitation on the degree to which a person modifies the landscape, in order to protect overall ecosystem quality. Leop...

  15. A Companion to Environmental Philosophy

    The land ethic as the next step in the Darwinian society-ethics pas de deux. The holism of the land ethic and its antecedents. The holism of the land ethic and the problem of eco-fascism. Prioritizing the duties generated by membership in multiple communities. The priority (second-order) principles applied to the old-growth forest quandary. The ...

  16. [PDF] The Land Ethic

    The Land Ethic. A. Leopold. Published 2014. History. When god-like Odysseus returned from the wars in Troy, he hanged all on one rope a dozen slave-girls of his household whom he suspected of misbehavior during his absence. View via Publisher. blogs.roosevelt.edu.

  17. Land Ethic Research Papers

    The main aim of this paper is to make some remarks about how Aldo Leopold and John Baird Callicott's land ethic handles the intentional killing of nonhuman animals by humans. I argue that the land ethic provides a more appropriate, less inconsistent, and more achievable ethical framework than the most of animal ethics to drive ethical ...

  18. PDF The Land Ethic

    A land ethic of course cannot prevent the alteration, management, and use of the "resources," but it does affirm their right to continued existence, and, at least in spots, their continued existence in a natural state. In short, a land ethic changes the role of Homo sapiens from conqueror of the land-

  19. Understanding the Land Ethic

    In A Sand County Almanac, Aldo Leopold set forth his most enduring idea, the "land ethic," a moral responsibility of humans to the natural world.Aldo Leopold's land ethic idea is extremely relevant in today's society, but understanding the land ethic can be difficult. This post will take a closer look at the basic tenets of Leopold's idea and explore how we can better understand and ...

  20. Positionality, relationality, place, and land: Considerations for

    Recognizing the often harmful and extractive legacies of the social sciences and academic research more broadly, a growing number of researchers are taking up questions around the ethics of doing research in, with, and for diverse communities (Paris and Winn, 2014; Tachine and Nicolazzo, 2022; Tuck, 2009).Emerging from these longstanding discussions is an increasing recognition of the need for ...

  21. Conducting Research with Tribal Communities: Sovereignty, Ethics, and

    Background: When conducting research with American Indian tribes, informed consent beyond conventional institutional review board (IRB) review is needed because of the potential for adverse consequences at a community or governmental level that are unrecognized by academic researchers.Objectives: In this article, we review sovereignty, research ethics, and data-sharing considerations when ...

  22. (PDF) Beyond the Land Ethic: More Essays in ...

    Fans of writers such as Leopold and Muir should, in contrast, nose through Callicott's essays on the great figures of American environmentalism in Beyond the Land Ethic, In a 264 Contents and Foci Callicott has prepared an introduction to Beyond the Land Ethic that provides a brief outline of his major topics, and he complains that academic ...

  23. Ethics in scientific research: a lens into its importance, history, and

    Introduction. Ethics are a guiding principle that shapes the conduct of researchers. It influences both the process of discovery and the implications and applications of scientific findings 1.Ethical considerations in research include, but are not limited to, the management of data, the responsible use of resources, respect for human rights, the treatment of human and animal subjects, social ...