Integration and Implementation Insights

Integration and Implementation Insights

A community blog and repository of resources for improving research impact on complex real-world problems

A guide to ontology, epistemology, and philosophical perspectives for interdisciplinary researchers

By Katie Moon and Deborah Blackman

katie-moon

How can understanding philosophy improve our research? How can an understanding of what frames our research influence our choices? Do researchers’ personal thoughts and beliefs shape research design, outcomes and interpretation?

These questions are all important for social science research. Here we present a philosophical guide for scientists to assist in the production of effective social science (adapted from Moon and Blackman, 2014).

deborah-blackman

Understanding philosophy is important because social science research can only be meaningfully interpreted when there is clarity about the decisions that were taken that affect the research outcomes. Some of these decisions are based, not always knowingly, on some key philosophical principles, as outlined in the figure below.

Philosophy provides the general principles of theoretical thinking, a method of cognition, perspective and self-awareness, all of which are used to obtain knowledge of reality and to design, conduct, analyse and interpret research and its outcomes. The figure below shows three main branches of philosophy that are important in the sciences and serves to illustrate the differences between them.

guide-to-ontology-moon

(Source: Moon and Blackman 2014)

The first branch is ontology, or the ‘study of being’, which is concerned with what actually exists in the world about which humans can acquire knowledge. Ontology helps researchers recognize how certain they can be about the nature and existence of objects they are researching. For instance, what ‘truth claims’ can a researcher make about reality? Who decides the legitimacy of what is ‘real’? How do researchers deal with different and conflicting ideas of reality?

To illustrate, realist ontology relates to the existence of one single reality which can be studied, understood and experienced as a ‘truth’; a real world exists independent of human experience. Meanwhile, relativist ontology is based on the philosophy that reality is constructed within the human mind, such that no one ‘true’ reality exists. Instead, reality is ‘relative’ according to how individuals experience it at any given time and place.

Epistemology

The second branch is epistemology, the ‘study of knowledge’. Epistemology is concerned with all aspects of the validity, scope and methods of acquiring knowledge, such as a) what constitutes a knowledge claim; b) how can knowledge be acquired or produced; and c) how the extent of its transferability can be assessed. Epistemology is important because it influences how researchers frame their research in their attempts to discover knowledge.

By looking at the relationship between a subject and an object we can explore the idea of epistemology and how it influences research design. Objectivist epistemology assumes that reality exists outside, or independently, of the individual mind. Objectivist research is useful in providing reliability (consistency of results obtained) and external validity (applicability of the results to other contexts).

Constructionist epistemology rejects the idea that objective ‘truth’ exists and is waiting to be discovered. Instead, ‘truth’, or meaning, arises in and out of our engagement with the realities in our world. That is, a ‘real world’ does not preexist independently of human activity or symbolic language. The value of constructionist research is in generating contextual understandings of a defined topic or problem.

Subjectivist epistemology relates to the idea that reality can be expressed in a range of symbol and language systems, and is stretched and shaped to fit the purposes of individuals such that people impose meaning on the world and interpret it in a way that makes sense to them. For example, a scuba diver might interpret a shadow in the water according to whether they were alerted to a shark in the area (the shark), waiting for a boat (the boat), or expecting a change in the weather (clouds). The value of subjectivist research is in revealing how an individual’s experience shapes their perception of the world.

Philosophical perspectives

Stemming from ontology (what exists for people to know about) and epistemology (how knowledge is created and what is possible to know) are philosophical perspectives, a system of generalized views of the world, which form beliefs that guide action.

Philosophical perspectives are important because, when made explicit, they reveal the assumptions that researchers are making about their research, leading to choices that are applied to the purpose, design, methodology and methods of the research, as well as to data analysis and interpretation. At the most basic level, the mere choice of what to study in the sciences imposes values on one’s subject.

Understanding the philosophical basis of science is critical in ensuring that research outcomes are appropriately and meaningfully interpreted. With an increase in interdisciplinary research, an examination of the points of difference and intersection between the philosophical approaches can generate critical reflection and debate about what we can know, what we can learn and how this knowledge can affect the conduct of science and the consequent decisions and actions.

How does your philosophical standpoint affect your research? What are your experiences of clashing philosophical perspectives in interdisciplinary research? How did you become aware of them and resolve them? Do you think that researchers need to recognize different philosophies in interdisciplinary research teams?

To find out more : Moon, K., and Blackman, D. (2014). A Guide to Understanding Social Science Research for Natural Scientists. Conservation Biology , 28 : 1167-1177. Online:  http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/cobi.12326/full

Biography: Katie Moon is a Post Doctoral Research Fellow at the University of New South Wales, Canberra. She is also an adjunct at the Institute for Applied Ecology at the University of Canberra. She has worked in the environmental policy arena for 17 years within Australia and Europe, in government, the private sector and academia. Her research focuses on how the right policy instruments can be paired to the right people; the role of evidence in policy development and implementation; and how to increase policy implementation success .

Biography: Deborah Blackman is a Professor in Public Sector Management Strategy and Deputy Director of the Public Service Research Group at the University of New South Wales, Canberra. She researches knowledge transfer in a range of applied, real world contexts. The common theme of her work is creating new organisational conversations in order to improve organisational effectiveness. This has included strengthening the performance management framework in the Australian Public Service; the role of social capital in long-term disaster recovery; and developing a new diagnostic model to support effective joined-up working in whole of government initiatives .

Related posts:

A guide for interdisciplinary researchers: Adding axiology alongside ontology and epistemology by Peter Deane https://i2insights.org/2018/05/22/axiology-and-interdisciplinarity/

Epistemological obstacles to interdisciplinary research by Evelyn Brister https://i2insights.org/2017/10/31/epistemology-and-interdisciplinarity/

Transforming transdisciplinarity: Interweaving the philosophical with the pragmatic to move beyond either/or thinking by Katie Ross and Cynthia Mitchell https://i2insights.org/2018/11/13/transdisciplinarity-and-either-or-thinking/

What is the role of theory in transdisciplinary research? by Workshop Group on Theory at 2015 Basel International Transdisciplinary Conference http://i2insights.org/2016/02/17/role-of-theory-in-transdisciplinary-research/

Share this:

13 thoughts on “a guide to ontology, epistemology, and philosophical perspectives for interdisciplinary researchers”.

Hi Katie and Deborah, First of all want to thank you for such incredible synthesis! Then I want to ask you, how can we situate a paradigm or an school or though in this map? For example, where do you think we can situate the complex paradigm of Edgar Morin? in between the relativistic ontology? or critical theory? thanks in advance.

  • Pingback: creative drift: on being natural - bob's thoughts, images, feelings

The table summary is admirable. All your write is very nice

  • Pingback: A guide to ontology, epistemology, and philosophical perspectives for interdisciplinary researchers | Learning Research Methods
  • Pingback: Week 2 – Ontology and Epistemology – Research Methods

Great post! I really like the table and find it a very helpful illustration!

Hi Kate, thank you very much for helping out. I understand the subject matter more now than before Olushola

  • Pingback: RES 701, Week 2, Ontology & Epistemology – RES701 Research Methods

Thanks so much for the debate and discussion around the blog post. Machiel is right in pointing out that the blog post (and the article it is based on) was intended as a conversation piece, and we’re pleased that a useful conversation is taking place. The resources and links are very helpful, philosophy is a fascinating discipline and the opportunity to learn and expand our thinking is endless.

We tried to make it clear in the article the blog post is based on that we wanted to bring attention to philosophy; it was obviously impossible to do the discipline of philosophy any real justice within 6,000 words. We wanted to start a conversation: “The purpose of the guide is to open the door to social science research and thus demonstrate that scientists can bring different and legitimate principles, assumptions, and interpretations to their research.”

As Jessica and Melissa point out, it can be challenging to offer social research to a natural science community that typically adopts a narrow philosophical position (e.g. objectivist). The paper was intended to encourage natural scientists to consider alternative ways of generating knowledge, particularly about the human, as opposed to natural, world.

We accept unequivocally that the framework does not get close to accommodating the depth and diversity of philosophy. Adam, we agree that the approach we have taken may not resonate with some philosophers, but we wanted to communicate with a particular audience (conservation scientists) and so we defined ontologies and epistemologies (and posited them relative to one another) that are most commonly observed within this discipline and that might be best understood by the audience. We tried to identify points of difference between ontologies, epistemologies and philosophical perspectives in an attempt to explain how they can influence research design. In the article, we use a case of deforestation in rainforests to demonstrate how different positions can influence the nature of the research questions and outcomes, including the assumptions that will be made.

We did explain in the introduction to our paper the limitations of our approach: “The multifaceted nature and interpretation of each of the concepts we present in our guide means they can be combined in a diversity of ways (see also Lincoln & Guba 2000; Schwandt 2000; Evely et al. 2008; H¨oijer 2008; Cunliffe 2011; Tang 2011). Therefore, our guide represents just one example of how the elements (i.e., different positions within the main branches of philosophy) of social research can apply specifically to conservation science. We recognize that by distilling and defining the elements in a simplified way we have necessarily constrained argument and debate surrounding each element. Furthermore, the guide had to have some structure. In forming this structure, we do not suggest that researchers must consider first their ontological and then their epistemological position and so on; they may well begin by exploring their philosophical perspective.”

This point comes back to Bruce’s comment, about pragmatic approaches to research. Often researchers pick and choose between a range of options that will allow them to define and answer their research questions in a way that makes most sense to them. We make this point in the paper: “Each perspective is characterized by an often wide ranging pluralism, which reflects the complex evolution of philosophy and the varied contributions of philosophers through time (Crotty 1998). All ontologies, epistemologies, and philosophical perspectives are characterized by this pluralism, including the prevailing (post) positivist approach of the natural sciences. It is common for more than one philosophical perspective to resonate with researchers and for researchers to change their perspective (and thus epistemological and ontological positions) toward their research over time (Moses & Knutsen 2012). Thus, scientists do not necessarily commit to one philosophical perspective and all associated characteristics (Bietsa 2010).”

We tried to anticipate concerns that scholars of philosophy might have with our rather reductionist approach, but felt that the more important contribution to make was to bring attention to alternative worldviews, and highlight the importance of philosophy in generating any type of knowledge.

With respect to the characterization of epistemologies, we adopted a continuum provided by Crotty (1998) that focuses on the relationship between the subject and the object. Again, this choice was made on the basis of our audience, to demonstrate that different types of relationship can exist between subject and object

This blog post has generated an interesting discussion on the Association for Interdisciplinary Studies listserv ([email protected]). Selected excerpts below.

Adam Potthast: I hate to make one of my first posts to this list critical without the time to correct some of the errors, but I don’t think you’d see many philosophers agreeing with the characterizations of philosophical views in this post. The infographic strongly mischaracterizes a lot of these positions, and the section on epistemology doesn’t map on to any of the standard understandings of epistemology in the discipline of philosophy. I’d caution against thinking of it as a reliable source to the philosophy behind science.

Gabriele Bammer: Thanks Adam for raising the alarm. It would be great if you and/or others who have problems with this post would spell out your criticisms – not only via this listserv, but (more importantly from my perspective) in a comment on the blog itself. Non-philosophers are hungry for a version of epistemology, ontology etc that they can understand and use and this blog post (and the paper it is based on) address this need. If it is seriously misleading though, that’s obviously a problem. It’s important that this is pointed out and that better alternatives are offered. I appreciate that time is an issue for everyone – anything you can do will be appreciated.

Stuart Henry: Well a good start, so we don’t reinvent the wheel again is James Welch’s article: https://oakland.edu/Assets/upload/docs/AIS/Issues-in-Interdisciplinary-Studies/2009-Volume-27/05_Vol_27_pp_35_69_Interdisciplinarity_and_the_History_of_Western_Epistemology_(James_Welch_IV) .pdf

Gabriele Bammer: Thanks Stuart, I may be missing something, but it seems to me that Welch’s article covers different terrain, being more about the philosophy underpinning interdisciplinarity. What Moon and Blackman provide is a quick guide to understanding people’s different philosophical positions, so that if you are working in a team, for example, you can better understand why someone sees the world differently. The Toolbox developed by Eigenbrode, O’Rourke and others provides a practical way of uncovering these differences.

Julie Thompson Klein: Good point Gabriele about the value of the Toolbox, though people still need the kind of background you’re aiming to provide.

Machiel Keestra: Although I agree that the blog post should perhaps not so much be taken to offer a current representation of the main positions in philosophy of science or about the interconnections between epistemological and ontological positions, I think it does a nice job in offering a conversation piece: what are relevant positions and options that people might -implicitly– take and how are they different from other positions. Given the modest ambitions of the authors, I think that is a fair result.

In addition to the interesting approach offered by the Toolbox Project, an alternative is presented in Jan Schmidt’s Towards a philosophy of interdisciplinarity: http://link.springer.com/article/10.1007%2Fs10202-007-0037-8 In our Introduction to interdisciplinary research, I’ve inserted an all-too brief philosophy of science which should help to raise some understanding of this difficult issue as well: https://www.academia.edu/22420234/An_Introduction_to_Interdisciplinary_Research._Theory_and_Practice

Lovely work! Thank you. I am also initially trained as a natural scientist, and now consider myself a ‘social-ecological researcher’ and have had to do a lot of learning about ontologies, epistemologies etc. I think I might use this paper as a discussion paper in our department as I think it is crucial for interdisciplinarians to understand these issues.

Kia ora Katie and Debbie, great post! I am a biophysical scientist who has come to social science and one of the struggles is being able to place the new and relevant concepts about questions that we don’t necessarily ask as biophysical scientists. Your table is a really useful aid to this – I immediately sent it to all my colleagues! It also makes it clearer to me how I can use the concept of triangulation that Bruce alluded to in his reply. So thank you for explaining so concisely. Thanks, Melissa

Hi Katie and Deborah,

Thank you for that discussion. I think that you have created a really useful table showing the philosophical continuums/polarities, how the various ontological and epistemological positions relate to each other, and the importance for researchers to be aware of them. In my own research practice, I am not committed to any one particular philosophical theory or perspective. They all appear to be true to some degree, that is, in some conceivable context – even though some of the concepts and philosophical positions appear, in the extreme form of their statement, to be contradictory, that is, if one end of a continuum/polarity is true then by implication it seems the other must be false – thus creating a quandary of research perspective. Hence the attraction, for me, of the application of a multiplicity of methods, approaches and philosophical perspectives – as and when they seem able to give ontological or epistemological insight – with triangulation between the results of the disparate approaches as the temporary arbiter of an evolving meaning and truth. This might be considered a pragmatic, perhaps even an opportunistic, approach to conducting science. However, as the old adage goes “the proof is in the pudding” – how useful is the knowledge obtained?

cheers Bruce

Leave a Reply Cancel reply

This site uses Akismet to reduce spam. Learn how your comment data is processed .

Discover more from Integration and Implementation Insights

Subscribe now to keep reading and get access to the full archive.

Type your email…

Continue reading

Relativism as an Ontological System

  • Original Paper
  • Published: 18 September 2021
  • Volume 32 , pages 1433–1449, ( 2022 )

Cite this article

relativist ontology qualitative research

  • Ihor Mykolayovych Rassokha 1  

2390 Accesses

Explore all metrics

A summary of a philosophical (ontological) system of consistent relativism based on the postulate of relativity of existence of all things in existence is proposed. Absolutely everything exists, but, at the same time, no existence is absolute. Anything is possible, but only those entities we interact with one way or another exist for us, i.e., reality is interaction, “I interact—hence, I exist”. For all of us, information, or perceptible heterogeneities, is real. There exists an infinity of different realities. The different levels of entities’ existence, in particular, of the Life and the Mind, should be taken into consideration. The existence of live systems in relation to non-living entities is undetermined, thus the alive can appear in its specifically live properties only through interaction with living things: there’s no difference between alive and dead for the stones. An even greater range of levels of existence can be brought about through interaction—that is the core idea of Gödel’s theorem. As a result, the range of forms of existence tends towards infinity—the evolution of matter through the Overmind will bring us up to God. This ontological position assumes a series of non-trivial physical conclusions, which can be tested experimentally, including the use of mathematical models. Rotation could be used to increase inertial mass and decrease gravitational mass, slowing down time. A more generalized mathematical model of the physical world, including a universal operator of the co-existence of objects, can be developed. In this model of Reality, superluminal speeds (without interaction) are possible and the Universe is open.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Subscribe and save.

  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or Ebook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime

Price includes VAT (Russian Federation)

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Rent this article via DeepDyve

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

relativist ontology qualitative research

The Fine-Tuning Argument: Exploring the Improbability of Our Existence

relativist ontology qualitative research

Foundations of a Theory of Gravity with a Constraint and Its Canonical Quantization

Quantum mechanics and the manifestation of the world.

Ashby WR (1957) An introduction to cybernetics. L.: Chapman and Hall Ltd

Berkley G (1953) The treatise on the principles of human knowledge, 1.3

Bertalanffy L von (1969) Obshchaya teoriya sistem—obzor problem i rezul'tatov//Sistemnyye issledovaniya: Yezhegodnik [The general theory of systems—a review of problems and results. System Studies: Yearbook]. Nauka, Moscow

Bogdanov AT (1989) Vseobshchaya organizatsionnaya nauka: v 2 kn. [ Tectology. General organizational science : in 2 books]. Book 1. Moskow: Ekonomika

Descartes R (1991). Discourse on the method of rightly conducting one's reason and of seeking truth in the sciences, Ch. 3

Dirak PAM (1984) The requirements of fundamental physical theory. Eur J Phys 5:65–67

Article   Google Scholar  

Everett H III (1983) The many–worlds interpretation of quantum mechanics. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ

Feynman RP (1965) The development of quantum electrodynamics in the spatio-temporal aspect. Nobel Lecture, December 11, 1965. https://www.nobelprize.org/prizes/physics/1965/feynman/lecture/

Glushkov V (1964) O kibernetike kak nauke // Kibernetika, myshleniye, zhizn' [On cybernetics as a science // Cybernetics, thinking, life ]. Mysl', Moskow

Mostepanenko AM (1987) Problema sushchestvovaniya v fizike i kosmologii: mirovozzrencheskiye i metodologicheskiye aspekty [The Problem of Existence in Physics and Cosmology: Worldview and Methodological Aspects]. Leningrad: Leningrad State University Publishing House, p. 7, 26, 13

Nikolay K (1984) O vozmozhnosti-bytii [Nicholas of Cusa. About Possibility-Being]. Nikolay Kuzanskiy. Soch. v dvukh tomakh. T. 2.—S. 135–182

Nietzsche F (1990) Genealogy of morality. First treatise: 'Good and Evil', 'Good and Bad'.

Novikov ID (1978) Equivalence, the principle. In: Great Soviet Encyclopedia, 3rd edn, vol 29, p 587

Rozhanskiy I (1983) Anaxagor. Mysl', Moskow

Schmutzer E (1981) Teoriya otnositel'nosti—sovremennoye predstavleniye. Put' k yedinstvu fiziki [Theory of relativity—a modern view. The path to the unity of physics]. Mir, Moskow

Ursul A (1968) Priroda informatsii: filosofskiy ocherk [The nature of information: a philosophical essay]. Izd-vo politicheskoy literatury, Moskow

Wayte R (2007) The phenomenon of weight-reduction of a spinning wheel. Meccanica 42(4):359–364

Download references

Author information

Authors and affiliations.

Department of Philosophy and Political Studies, O. M. Beketov National University of the Urban Economy in Kharkiv, 17, Marshal Bazhanov Street, Kharkiv, 61002, Ukraine

Ihor Mykolayovych Rassokha

You can also search for this author in PubMed   Google Scholar

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ihor Mykolayovych Rassokha .

Additional information

Publisher's note.

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Rassokha, I.M. Relativism as an Ontological System. Axiomathes 32 , 1433–1449 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10516-021-09589-w

Download citation

Received : 19 February 2021

Accepted : 15 August 2021

Published : 18 September 2021

Issue Date : December 2022

DOI : https://doi.org/10.1007/s10516-021-09589-w

Share this article

Anyone you share the following link with will be able to read this content:

Sorry, a shareable link is not currently available for this article.

Provided by the Springer Nature SharedIt content-sharing initiative

  • “Postmodernism”
  • “Everything exists”
  • Information
  • Quantum theory
  • Find a journal
  • Publish with us
  • Track your research
-->
> >

- assumes that reality as we know it is constructed intersubjectively through the meanings and understandings developed socially and experientially. - assumes that we cannot separate ourselves from what we know.  The investigator and the object of investigation are linked such that who we are and how we understand the world is a central part of how we understand ourselves, others and the world.

- recognition that the choices we make through the research process have political and ethical consideration.  - evaluting the substance or content of an interpretive work

. 10(3) pp. 378-395.

. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.

. Garden City, NY: Doubleday and Company.

. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

. New York: Free Press.

. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.

. Chicago: Aldine.

. pp. 105-117.

. Theory and History of Literature. Volume 10. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.

. New York: Harcourt, Brace & World.      

, Volume 1, The Hague, Martinus Nijhoff. : "Commonsense and scientific interpretations of human action" pp. 3-47; "Concept and theory formation in the social sciences" pp. 48-66; "On multiple realities" pp. 207-259.

(GEM Anscome transl). Third Edition. Englewood Cliffs, NJ. Prentice-Hall.

to go back to Common Paradigms


© RWJF 2008
P.O. Box 2316 College Road East and Route 1
Princeton, NJ 08543





-->Citation: Cohen D, Crabtree B. "Qualitative Research Guidelines Project." July 2006.


Last updated 27/06/24: Online ordering is currently unavailable due to technical issues. We apologise for any delays responding to customers while we resolve this. For further updates please visit our website: https://www.cambridge.org/news-and-insights/technical-incident

We use cookies to distinguish you from other users and to provide you with a better experience on our websites. Close this message to accept cookies or find out how to manage your cookie settings .

Login Alert

relativist ontology qualitative research

  • > Relativism
  • > Ontological relativism

relativist ontology qualitative research

Book contents

  • Frontmatter
  • 1 Introduction to relativism
  • 2 Truth and logic
  • 3 Ontological relativism
  • 4 Epistemological relativism
  • 5 Relativism about rationality
  • 6 Evaluating relativism
  • Guide to further reading
  • Bibliography

3 - Ontological relativism

What is ontological relativism?

Ontology is that part of philosophy which investigates the fundamental structures of the world and the fundamental kinds of things that exist. Terms like “object”, “fact”, “property”, “relation” and “category” are technical terms used to make sense of these most basic features of reality. Until Kant, there was widespread agreement on the framework for debates about ontology, and varying accounts of existence, essence, substance and property were articulated and defended. This involved some of the great debates of Western philosophy, for example about the status of universals. However, amid these differences were shared aims (finding out the fundamental nature of reality) and shared methods (dialectical argumentation). Those philosophers who abstained from these debates did so from the position of scepticism, holding that we just don't have the cognitive wherewithal to decide any of these issues. Nevertheless, there was clear agreement on all sides that ontology had to do with portraying the nature of reality: telling it as it really is. Kant upset this consensus. His Copernican revolution introduced a new dimension to the debate. His suggestion was that ontology has to do with articulating the nature of reality as known to human cognition , not as it is in itself . In common with sceptics he denies our access to a world in itself. However, unlike sceptics, he believes there is still a point to doing ontology and still an account to be given of the basic structures by which the world is revealed to us.

Access options

Save book to kindle.

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle .

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service .

  • Ontological relativism
  • Paul O'Grady , Trinity College, Dublin
  • Book: Relativism
  • Online publication: 05 February 2013
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/UPO9781844653294.004

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox .

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive .

strategicjournals.com

  • For Readers
  • For Authors
  • For Librarians
  • Announcements

QUALITATIVE RESEARCH METHODOLOGY IN SOCIAL SCIENCE RESEARCH: TOWARDS RELATIVIST ONTOLOGY AND INTERPRETIVIST-CONSTRUCTIVIST EPISTEMOLOGY

This paper examined qualitative research methodology and its suitability for social science research. It argued for adoption of relativist ontology and interpretivist-constructivist epistemology within the realm of qualitative Research Methodology. It first focused on quantitative research methodologies and their limitations in social science research before outlining qualitative methodologies and their applicability. It concluded that qualitative methodologies are essential in humanistic inquiry.

Key Words: Relativist Ontology, Interpretivist-Constructivist Epistemology

Braun, V. and Clarke, V. (2006). Using Thematic Analysis in Psychology. Qualitative Research in Psychology.3:77-101

Creswell, J. W. (2009) Qualitative, Quantitative, and Mixed Methods Approaches (3rd edition) Thousand Oaks, CA Sage Publications.

Creswell, J. W. (2003) Qualitative, Quantitative, and Mixed Methods Approaches (2rd edition) Thousand Oaks, CA Sage Publications.

Denzin, N and Lincoln, Y (Eds) (1994) Handbook of Qualitative Research, Thousand Oaks (Calif), Sage

Elliot J. (2005) Using Narrative in Social Science Research Sage Publishers London.

Glaser, B.G. (2003). Naturalist Inquiry and Grounded Theory. Forum: Qualitative Social Research, 5(1) Art. 7

Gregory, Currie. (2010) Narratives and Narrators: A Philosophy of Stories Oxford University Press

Hesse-Biber, S. N & Leavy (Ed) (2004) Patricia Approaches to Qualitative Research, Oxford University Press

Holloway Immy (1997) Basic Concepts for Qualitative Research. Wiley Press

Josselson, R., & Lieblich, A., & McAdams, D. P. (Eds.) (2003) Up Close and Personal: The Teaching and Learning of Narrative Research. Washington, DC: American Psychological Association

Jwan O. and On’gondo O. (2011).Qualitative Research: An Introduction To Principles And Techniques. Eldoret: Moi University Press

Kvale, S.(1996). Interviews: An Introduction to Qualitative Research Interviewing Thousand Oaks California: Sage Publications.

Lacey, A., and Luff, D. (2001). Trent Focus for Research and Development in Primary Health Care: An Introduction to Qualitative Analysis. Trent Focus.

Mason, Jennifer. (2002). Qualitative Researching (2nd Ed). London: Sage

Moen Torill (2006) Reflection on Narrative Research Approach International Journal of Qualitative Methods Vol. 5. No. 4.

Morgan, D. L. (1998).The Focus Group Guidebook. Thousand Oaks. Ca: Sage Publications.

Patton, M.Q. (2002). Qualitative Research and Evaluation Methods (3rd Ed). London:Sage

Sandelowski, M. (1995) Sample Size I Qualitative Research in Research in Nursing and Health Vol. 18, issue 4

Stacy, R.H. 1977. Defamiliarization in Language and Literature. Syracuse: Syracuse University Press.

VSO. (2002). How Much is a Good Teacher Worth? A Report on the Motivation and Morale of Teachers in Ethiopia.Valuing Teachers.

  • There are currently no refbacks.
     
        
           

Creative Commons License

Logo for OPEN OKSTATE

Interpretivism

Often contrasted with Positivism is Interpretivism. The starting point for Interpretivism – which is sometimes called Anti-Positivism – is that knowledge in the human and social sciences cannot conform to the model of natural science because there are features of human experience that cannot objectively be “known”. This might include emotions; understandings; values; feelings; subjectivities; socio-cultural factors; historical influence; and other meaningful aspects of human being. Instead of finding “truth” the Interpretivist aims to generate understanding and often adopts a relativist position.

Qualitative methods are preferred as ways to investigate these phenomena. Data collected might be unstructured (or “messy”) and correspondingly a range of techniques for approaching data collection have been developed. Interpretivism acknowledges that it is impossible to remove cultural and individual influence from research, often instead making a virtue of the positionality of the researcher and the socio-cultural context of a study.

One key consideration here is the purported validity of qualitative research. Interpretivism tends to emphasize the subjective over the objective. If the starting point for an investigation is that we can’t fully and objectively know the world, how can we do research into this without everything being a matter of opinion? Essentially Positivism and Interpretivism retain different ontologies and epistemologies with contrasting notions of rigour and validity (in the broadest rather than statistical sense). Interpretivist research often embraces a relativist epistemology, bringing together different perspectives in search of an overall understanding or narrative.

Kivunja & Kuyini (2017) describe the essential features of Interpretivism as:

  • The admission that the social world cannot be understood from the standpoint of an individual
  • The belief that realities are multiple and socially constructed
  • The acceptance that there is inevitable interaction between the researcher and his or her research participants
  • The acceptance that context is vital for knowledge and knowing.
  • The belief that knowledge is created by the findings, can be value laden and the values need to be made explicit
  • The need to understand the individual rather than universal laws
  • The belief that causes and effects are mutually interdependent
  • The belief that contextual factors need to be taken into consideration in any systematic pursuit of understanding

Interpretivism as a research paradigm is often accompanied by Constructivism as an ontological and epistemological grounding. Many learning theories emphasize Constructivism as an organising principle, and Constructivism often underlies aspects of educational research.

Interpretivist Methods : Case Studies; Conversational analysis; Delphi; Description; Document analysis; Interviews; Focus Groups; Grounded theory; Phenomenography; Phenomenology; Thematic analysis

[INSERT Figure 2]

methodological aspects of Positivism and Interpretivism. Positivism Interpretivism Ontology Being in the world Direct access (Naturalism) Indirect access (Idealism) Reality Objective, accessible Subjectively experienced Epistemology Relation between knowledge and reality Objective knowledge of the world is possible supported by appropriate method Objective knowledge of the world is possible supported by appropriate method Epistemological goals Generalisation, abstraction, discovery of law-like relationships Knowledge of specific, concrete cases and examples Basic approach Hypothesis formation and testing Describing and seeking to understand phenomena in context Methodology Focus Description and explanation Understanding and interpretation Research Perspective Detached, objective Embedded in the phenomena under investigation Role of emotions Strict separation between the cognitions and feeling of the researchers Emotional response can be part of coming to understanding Limits of researcher influence Discovery of external, objective reality – minimal influence Object of study is potentially influenced by the activity of the researcher Valued approaches Consistency, clarity, reproducibility, rationality, lack of bias Insight, appreciation of context and prior understanding Fact/value distinction Clear distinction between facts and values Distinction is less rigid, acknowledges entanglement Archetypal research methods Quantitative (e.g. statistical analysis) Qualitative (e.g. case study) Figure 2. Ontology, Epistemology and Methodology across Positivism and Interpretivism (adapted from Carson et al., 2001)

Research Methods Handbook Copyright © 2020 by Rob Farrow; Francisco Iniesto; Martin Weller; and Rebecca Pitt is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License , except where otherwise noted.

Share This Book

COMMENTS

  1. Philosophical Paradigms, Grounded Theory, and Perspectives on Emergence

    Using ontological and epistemological positions to develop three research paradigms, and applying these paradigms to various uptakes of grounded theory demonstrates differences in the definition of emergence. Discovery emergence is presented as a unidirectional relationship between the constituent parts (data) and the emergent property (theory ...

  2. International Journal of Qualitative Methods Comparisons of Adaptations

    The most widely used qualitative research methodologies are grounded theory and phenomenology. Both methodologies have ... paradigm is often described with a relativist ontology (a worldview that multiple realities exist) and a subjectivist epistemology that truth and meaning are shared subjectively

  3. A guide to ontology, epistemology, and philosophical perspectives for

    To illustrate, realist ontology relates to the existence of one single reality which can be studied, understood and experienced as a 'truth'; a real world exists independent of human experience. Meanwhile, relativist ontology is based on the philosophy that reality is constructed within the human mind, such that no one 'true' reality ...

  4. Philosophical Paradigms, Grounded Theory, and Perspectives on Emergence

    As the qualitative research world continues to move through the "moments" as defined by Denzin and Lincoln (2005), nursing research seems to be moving further away ... Relativist ontology is the belief that reality is a finite sub-jective experience (Denzin & Lincoln, 2005) and nothing exists outside of our thoughts. Reality from a ...

  5. PDF Philosophical Assumptions

    In qualitative research, interviewing is one of the most frequently used methods when generating data. Other methods could include, for example, observation, diaries, the generation of visual images or other forms ... Relativist ontology rejects such direct explanations, maintaining that the world is far more unstructured and diverse. Our ...

  6. PDF What Is Realism, and Why Should Qualitative Researchers Care?

    6—PART I A REALIST STANCE FOR QUALITATIVE RESEARCH Campbell (2002) argued that "all scientists are epistemological constructivists and relativists" in the sense that they believe that both the ontological world and the worlds of ideology, values, etc. play a role in the construction of sci-entific knowledge (p. 29).

  7. Theory and application of research principles and philosophical

    Qualitative research approaches have potential to provide unique and valuable insights intoperceptions, experiences and behaviours. ... Relativist ontology and Subjectivist epistemology. This said there is a degree of overlap which affords flexibility but requires researchers to provide their justification for selection of choice for their own ...

  8. PDF The Ontological and Epistemological Foundations of Qualitative and

    Bryman (2004) identifies two ontological positions concerning social research, 'objectivism' and 'constructionism'. According to Bryman, objectivism entails that the social entity in question adheres to an external objective reality independent of the researcher's awareness.

  9. Philosophical Paradigms in Qualitative Research Methods Education: What

    qualitative methods than Kuhn's theory. According to Guba and Lincoln, paradigms consist of "basic beliefs" (Guba & Lincoln, 1994, p. 107). Researchers hold beliefs about what exists and how knowledge is possible, and these beliefs determine how researchers choose to conduct inquiry.

  10. Relativism as an Ontological System

    A summary of a philosophical (ontological) system of consistent relativism based on the postulate of relativity of existence of all things in existence is proposed. Absolutely everything exists, but, at the same time, no existence is absolute. Anything is possible, but only those entities we interact with one way or another exist for us, i.e., reality is interaction, "I interact—hence, I ...

  11. (PDF) A Review of key paradigms: positivism, interpretivism and

    Interpretivism was employed to adapt a relativist ontology for multiple interpretations of a single phenomenon to gain a deeper understanding of the subject matter. ... The qualitative research ...

  12. Capturing Lived Experience: Methodological Considerations for

    A constructivist paradigm orients phenomenological research by way of a relativist ontology whereby human "realities are apprehended in the form of multiple, intangible mental constructions, socially and experientially based, local and specific in nature" (Guba & Lincoln, 1994, p. 110).

  13. RWJF

    relativist ontology - assumes that reality as we know it is constructed intersubjectively through the meanings and understandings ... YS. (1994). "Competing paradigms in qualitative research." In NK Denzin and YS Lincoln (eds.) Handbook of Qualitative Research. pp. 105-117. Lyotard, J. (1979). The Postmodern Condition: A report on Knowledge ...

  14. 3

    Summary. What is ontological relativism? Ontology is that part of philosophy which investigates the fundamental structures of the world and the fundamental kinds of things that exist. Terms like "object", "fact", "property", "relation" and "category" are technical terms used to make sense of these most basic features of ...

  15. PDF Understanding Research Paradigms: An Ontological Perspective to

    Understanding Research Paradigms: An Ontological Perspective to Business Research Toritseju Rita Pessu ... (Saunders et al., 2016). The relativist position asserts that each person has their different view of reality that is considered right (Easterby-Smith et al., 2012). ... qualitative research focuses on examining the findings generated from ...

  16. Qualitative Research Methodology in Social Science Research: Towards

    This paper examined qualitative research methodology and its suitability for social science research. It argued for adoption of relativist ontology and interpretivist-constructivist epistemology within the realm of qualitative Research Methodology.It first focused on quantitative research methodologies and their limitations in social science research before outlining qualitative methodologies ...

  17. Thinking through and designing qualitative research studies: a focused

    ologies used in qualitative research in sport psychology, as well as the increase in qualitat-ive research between 1990-1999 and 2000-2009. However, as with any study, there were some limitations to the reviews from Culver and colleagues (2003, 2012). For example, these reviews examined the prevalence of qualitative research across two ...

  18. Challenging Relativism: The Problem of Assessment Criteria

    This article raises serious questions about the relativist approach to assessing qualitative research that has been championed by John K. Smith and various colleagues. They reject not just empiricism but also what they refer to as "neorealism.". Against both these positions, they advance an antirealist, anti-ontological argument to the ...

  19. Interpretivism

    Kivunja & Kuyini (2017) describe the essential features of Interpretivism as: The admission that the social world cannot be understood from the standpoint of an individual. The belief that realities are multiple and socially constructed. The acceptance that there is inevitable interaction between the researcher and his or her research participants.

  20. Reconsidering Constructivism in Qualitative Research

    A relativist ontology states that there are multiple, diverse, and varied realities (Lee 2012) and a constructivist epistemology holds that individuals construct and create their knowledge, and ...

  21. Full article: Thinking through and designing qualitative research

    Methodology. The methodology selected for this review was a 'focused mapping review and synthesis' because we focused on (a) a particular subject, (b) a defined time period, and (c) specific journals (Bradbury-Jones et al., Citation 2017; Grant & Booth, Citation 2009).The characteristics of a focused mapping review and synthesis methodology are well-suited for the present study given our ...

  22. The Development of Constructivist Grounded Theory

    Constructivist grounded theory is a popular method for research studies primarily in the disciplines of psychology, education, and nursing. In this article, the authors aim to locate the roots of constructivist grounded theory and then trace its development. They examine key grounded theory texts to discern their ontological and epistemological ...

  23. Comparisons of Adaptations in Grounded Theory and Phenomenology

    Qualitative research methodologies are the specified philosophical and theoretical frameworks applied in a systematic inquiry into social phenomena in a natural setting (Creswell & Poth, 2018).The most widely used qualitative research methodologies are grounded theory and phenomenology (Gelling, 2011; Goulding, 2005; Padgett, 2017; Strandmark, 2015).

  24. Staying isolated indoors means that nobody sees me": ontological (in

    Dr Richardson is a qualitative researcher whose work focuses on improving access and equity to physical activity opportunities among disabled communities. Prior and ongoing research include how gyms, rehabilitation spaces, sport and physical education can be made more inclusive of individual with physical impairments and/or chronic illness.

  25. An Anti-Racist Critique Related to the Ontology and Epistemology of

    Therefore, I problematize three aspects of qualitative research, that is, the standard qualitative research model that came out of the 1980s to early 1990s, the focus on the individual as the font of "truth," and coding and thematizing, all of which arises within the systemic White supremacy racism of Modernity.