Insights into embodied cognition and mental imagery from aphantasia

  • Emiko J. Muraki   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0001-9534-6538 1 , 2 ,
  • Laura J. Speed   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0002-3147-3615 3 &
  • Penny M. Pexman   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0001-7130-0973 1 , 2  

Nature Reviews Psychology volume  2 ,  pages 591–605 ( 2023 ) Cite this article

1243 Accesses

4 Citations

37 Altmetric

Metrics details

  • Behavioural methods
  • Language and linguistics

Mental representations allow humans to think about, remember and communicate about an infinite number of concepts. A key question within cognitive psychology is how the mind stores and accesses the meaning of concepts. Embodied theories propose that concept knowledge includes or requires simulations of the sensory and physical interactions of one’s body with the world, even when a concept is subsequently processed in a context unrelated to those interactions. However, the nature of these simulations is highly debated and their mechanisms underspecified. Insight into whether and how simulations support concept knowledge can be derived from studying related mental representations, such as mental imagery. In particular, research into the inability to form mental imagery, known as aphantasia, can advance understanding of mental imagery and mental simulations. In this Review, we provide an overview of embodied theories of cognition, review research in mental imagery and consider how simulation and mental imagery might overlap. We then synthesize the growing aphantasia literature and discuss how aphantasia can be used to test predictions derived from theories of embodied cognition.

This is a preview of subscription content, access via your institution

Access options

Subscribe to this journal

Receive 12 digital issues and online access to articles

55,14 € per year

only 4,60 € per issue

Buy this article

  • Purchase on Springer Link
  • Instant access to full article PDF

Prices may be subject to local taxes which are calculated during checkout

mental representation

Similar content being viewed by others

mental representation

A cognitive profile of multi-sensory imagery, memory and dreaming in aphantasia

mental representation

The human imagination: the cognitive neuroscience of visual mental imagery

mental representation

Reverse-engineering the cortical architecture for controlled semantic cognition

Pearson, J., Naselaris, T., Holmes, E. A. & Kosslyn, S. M. Mental imagery: functional mechanisms and clinical applications. Trends Cogn. Sci. 19 , 590–602 (2015).

Article   PubMed   PubMed Central   Google Scholar  

Zeman, A. Z. J. et al. Loss of imagery phenomenology with intact visuo-spatial task performance: a case of ‘blind imagination’. Neuropsychologia 48 , 145–155 (2010).

Article   PubMed   Google Scholar  

Zeman, A., Dewar, M. & Della Sala, S. Lives without imagery — congenital aphantasia. Cortex 73 , 378–380 (2015). This article is among the first to describe and characterize congenital aphantasia, the lifelong absence of mental imagery.

Wilson, M. Six views of embodied cognition. Psychon. Bull. Rev. 9 , 625–636 (2002).

Barsalou, L. W. Grounded cognition. Annu. Rev. Psychol. 59 , 617–645 (2008). This article describes the theoretical foundation of embodied cognition as it relates to several cognitive processes and reviews the empirical literature testing embodied theories of cognition.

Mahon, B. Z. & Caramazza, A. A critical look at the embodied cognition hypothesis and a new proposal for grounding conceptual content. J. Physiol.-Paris 102 , 59–70 (2008).

Ostarek, M. & Bottini, R. Towards strong inference in research on embodiment — possibilities and limitations of causal paradigms. J. Cogn. 4 , 1–21 (2020). This article critiques empirical evidence for embodied conceptual processing and proposes methodological approaches to better understand the causal relationship between sensory experience and conceptual processing.

Google Scholar  

Dawes, A. J., Keogh, R., Robuck, S. & Pearson, J. Memories with a blind mind: remembering the past and imagining the future with aphantasia. Cognition 227 , 105192 (2022).

Fodor, J. A. The Language of Thought Vol. 5 (Harvard Univ. Press, 1975).

Pylyshyn, Z. Computation and cognition: issues in the foundations of cognitive science. Behav. Brain Sci. 3 , 111–169 (1980).

Article   Google Scholar  

Anderson, J. R. Arguments concerning representations for mental imagery. Psychol. Rev. 85 , 249–277 (1978).

Pylyshyn, Z. W. What the mind’s eye tells the mind’s brain: a critique of mental imagery. Psychol. Bull. 80 , 1–24 (1973).

Zwaan, R. A. The immersed experiencer: toward an embodied theory of language comprehension. Psychol. Learn. Motiv. 44 , 35–62 (2004).

Meteyard, L., Cuadrado, S. R., Bahrami, B. & Vigliocco, G. Coming of age: a review of embodiment and the neuroscience of semantics. Cortex 48 , 788–804 (2012). This article describes the spectrum of theories related to embodied and non-embodied semantic representation, linking behavioural and neural evidence with the theories.

Collins, A. M. & Loftus, E. F. A spreading-activation theory of semantic processing. Psychol. Rev. 82 , 407 (1975).

Quillian, M. R. Word concepts: a theory and simulation of some basic semantic capabilities. Behav. Sci. 12 , 410–430 (1967).

Quillian, R. A revised design for an understanding machine. Mech. Transl. 7 , 17–29 (1962).

Patterson, K. & Lambon Ralph, M. A. in Neurobiology of Language Ch. 61 (eds Hickok, G. & Small, S. L.) 765–775 (Academic, 2016).

Barsalou, L. W., Santos, A., Simmons, W. K. & Wilson, C. D. in Symbols, Embodiment, and Meaning (eds De Vega, M., Glenberg, A. M. & Graesser, A. C.) 245–283 (Oxford Univ. Press, 2008).

Connell, L. What have labels ever done for us? The linguistic shortcut in conceptual processing. Lang. Cogn. Neurosci. 34 , 1308–1318 (2019).

Paivio, A. Imagery and Verbal Processes (Holt, Rinehart and Winston, 1971).

Paivio, A. Mental imagery in associative learning and memory. Psychol. Rev. 76 , 241–263 (1969).

Balota, D. A., Cortese, M. J., Sergent-Marshall, S. D., Spieler, D. H. & Yap, M. J. Visual word recognition of single-syllable words. J. Exp. Psychol.-Gen. 133 , 283–316 (2004).

Barsalou, L. W. Perceptual symbol systems. Behav. Brain Sci. 22 , 577–660 (1999).

Glenberg, A. M. & Gallese, V. Action-based language: a theory of language acquisition, comprehension, and production. Cortex 48 , 905–922 (2012).

Brysbaert, M., Warriner, A. B. & Kuperman, V. Concreteness ratings for 40 thousand generally known English word lemmas. Behav. Res. Methods 46 , 904–911 (2014).

Lynott, D., Connell, L., Brysbaert, M., Brand, J. & Carney, J. The lancaster sensorimotor norms: multidimensional measures of perceptual and action strength for 40,000 English words. Behav. Res. Methods 52 , 1271–1291 (2020).

Pexman, P. M., Muraki, E., Sidhu, D. M., Siakaluk, P. D. & Yap, M. J. Quantifying sensorimotor experience: body-object interaction ratings for more than 9,000 English words. Behav. Res. Methods 51 , 453–466 (2019).

Balota, D. A. et al. The English Lexicon Project. Behav. Res. Methods 39 , 445–459 (2007).

Siakaluk, P. D., Pexman, P. M., Aguilera, L., Owen, W. J. & Sears, C. R. Evidence for the activation of sensorimotor information during visual word recognition: the body–object interaction effect. Cognition 106 , 433–443 (2008).

Sidhu, D. M., Kwan, R., Pexman, P. M. & Siakaluk, P. D. Effects of relative embodiment in lexical and semantic processing of verbs. Acta Psychol. 149 , 32–39 (2014).

Pecher, D., Zeelenberg, R. & Barsalou, L. W. Verifying different-modality properties for concepts produces switching costs. Psychol. Sci. 14 , 119–124 (2003).

Pecher, D., Zeelenberg, R. & Barsalou, L. W. Sensorimotor simulations underlie conceptual representations: modality-specific effects of prior activation. Psychon. Bull. Rev. 11 , 164–167 (2004).

Dove, G. Three symbol ungrounding problems: abstract concepts and the future of embodied cognition. Psychon. Bull. Rev. 23 , 1109–1121 (2016).

Louwerse, M. M. Symbol interdependency in symbolic and embodied cognition. Top. Cogn. Sci. 3 , 273–302 (2011).

Glenberg, A. M. & Kaschak, M. P. Grounding language in action. Psychon. Bull. Rev. 9 , 558–565 (2002).

Stanfield, R. A. & Zwaan, R. The effect of implied orientation derived from verbal context on picture recognition. Psychol. Sci. 12 , 153–156 (2001).

Morey, R. D. et al. A pre-registered, multi-lab non-replication of the action-sentence compatibility effect (ACE). Psychon. Bull. Rev. 29 , 613–626 (2021).

Winter, A. The action–sentence compatibility effect (ACE): meta-analysis of a benchmark finding for embodiment. Acta Psychol. 230 , 103712 (2022).

Muraki, E. J. & Pexman, P. M. Simulating semantics: are individual differences in motor imagery related to sensorimotor effects in language processing? J. Exp. Psychol. Learn. Mem. Cogn. 47 , 1939–1957 (2021).

Zwaan, R. A. & Pecher, D. Revisiting mental simulation in language comprehension: six replication attempts. PLoS ONE 7 , e51382 (2012).

Beveridge, M. E. L. & Pickering, M. J. Perspective taking in language: integrating the spatial and action domains. Front. Hum. Neurosci. 7 , 577 (2013).

Hargreaves, I. S., White, M., Pexman, P. M., Pittman, D. & Goodyear, B. G. The question shapes the answer: the neural correlates of task differences reveal dynamic semantic processing. Brain Lang. 120 , 73–78 (2012).

Tousignant, C. & Pexman, P. Flexible recruitment of semantic richness: context modulates body–object interaction effects in lexical-semantic processing. Front. Hum. Neurosci. 6 , 7 (2012).

van Dam, W. O., van Dijk, M., Bekkering, H. & Rueschemeyer, S.-A. Flexibility in embodied lexical-semantic representations. Hum. Brain Mapp. 33 , 2322–2333 (2012).

Reifegerste, J., Meyer, A. S., Zwitserlood, P. & Ullman, M. T. Aging affects steaks more than knives: evidence that the processing of words related to motor skills is relatively spared in aging. Brain Lang. 218 , 104941 (2021).

Simonsen, H. G., Lind, M., Hansen, P., Holm, E. & Mevik, B. H. Imageability of Norwegian nouns, verbs and adjectives in a cross-linguistic perspective. Clin. Linguist. Phon. 27 , 435–446 (2013).

Ibáñez, A. et al. Ecological meanings: a consensus paper on individual differences and contextual influences in embodied language. Preprint at OSF https://osf.io/ej5y3/ (2022).

Andrews, M., Vigliocco, G. & Vinson, D. Integrating experiential and distributional data to learn semantic representations. Psychol. Rev. 116 , 463–498 (2009).

Banks, B., Wingfield, C. & Connell, L. Linguistic distributional knowledge and sensorimotor grounding both contribute to semantic category production. Cogn. Sci. 45 , e13055 (2021).

Henningsen-Schomers, M. R., Garagnani, M. & Pulvermüller, F. Influence of language on perception and concept formation in a brain-constrained deep neural network model. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. B Biol. Sci. 378 , 20210373 (2023).

Barsalou, L. W. Challenges and opportunities for grounding cognition. J. Cogn. 3 , 31 (2020).

Ostarek, M. & Huettig, F. A task-dependent causal role for low-level visual processes in spoken word comprehension. J. Exp. Psychol. Learn. Mem. Cogn. 43 , 1215–1224 (2017).

Kuhnke, P., Beaupain, M. C., Arola, J., Kiefer, M. & Hartwigsen, G. Meta-analytic evidence for a novel hierarchical model of conceptual processing. Neurosci. Biobehav. Rev . 144 , 104994 (2022). This article reports a meta-analysis examining the role of modal regions in conceptual processing.

Gallese, V. Mirror neurons and the social nature of language: the neural exploitation hypothesis. Soc. Neurosci. 3 , 317–333 (2008).

Pulvermüller, F. Semantic embodiment, disembodiment or misembodiment? In search of meaning in modules and neuron circuits. Brain Lang. 127 , 86–103 (2013).

Barsalou, L. W. On staying grounded and avoiding quixotic dead ends. Psychon. Bull. Rev. 23 , 1122–1142 (2016).

Barsalou, L. W. Establishing generalizable mechanisms. Psychol. Inq. 30 , 220–230 (2019).

Bottini, R., Morucci, P., D’Urso, A., Collignon, O. & Crepaldi, D. The concreteness advantage in lexical decision does not depend on perceptual simulations. J. Exp. Psychol. Gen. 151 , 731–738 (2022).

Boulenger, V. et al. Word processing in Parkinson’s disease is impaired for action verbs but not for concrete nouns. Neuropsychologia 46 , 743–756 (2008).

Buccino, G. et al. Processing graspable object images and their nouns is impaired in Parkinson’s disease patients. Cortex 100 , 32–39 (2018).

García, A. M. et al. Parkinson’s disease compromises the appraisal of action meanings evoked by naturalistic texts. Cortex 100 , 111–126 (2018).

García, A. M. et al. How language flows when movements don’t: an automated analysis of spontaneous discourse in Parkinson’s disease. Brain Lang. 162 , 19–28 (2016).

Nistico, R. et al. The embodiment of language in tremor-dominant Parkinson’s disease patients. Brain Cogn. 135 , 103586 (2019).

Trumpp, N. M., Kliese, D., Hoenig, K., Haarmeier, T. & Kiefer, M. Losing the sound of concepts: damage to auditory association cortex impairs the processing of sound-related concepts. Cortex 49 , 474–486 (2013).

Kim, J. S., Elli, G. V. & Bedny, M. Knowledge of animal appearance among sighted and blind adults. Proc. Natl Acad. Sci. USA 116 , 11213–11222 (2019).

Lewis, M., Zettersten, M. & Lupyan, G. Distributional semantics as a source of visual knowledge. Proc. Natl Acad. Sci. USA 116 , 19237–19238 (2019).

Nanay, B. Multimodal mental imagery. Cortex 105 , 125–134 (2018).

Pearson, J. The human imagination: the cognitive neuroscience of visual mental imagery. Nat. Rev. Neurosci. 20 , 624–634 (2019). This article provides an overview of the neural bases of visual imagery.

Pearson, J. & Westbrook, F. Phantom perception: voluntary and involuntary nonretinal vision. Trends Cogn. Sci. 19 , 278–284 (2015).

Kwok, E. L., Leys, G., Koenig-Robert, R. & Pearson, J. Measuring thought-control failure: sensory mechanisms and individual differences. Psychol. Sci. 30 , 811–821 (2019).

Jeannerod, M. Neural simulation of action: a unifying mechanism for motor cognition. Neuroimage 14 , S103–S109 (2001).

Willems, R. M., Toni, I., Hagoort, P. & Casasanto, D. Neural dissociations between action verb understanding and motor imagery. J. Cogn. Neurosci. 22 , 2387–2400 (2009).

Connell, L. & Lynott, D. Do we know what we’re simulating? Information loss on transferring unconscious perceptual simulation to conscious imagery. J. Exp. Psychol. Learn. Mem. Cogn. 42 , 1218–1232 (2016).

Pearson, J. & Kosslyn, S. M. The heterogeneity of mental representation: ending the imagery debate. Proc. Natl Acad. Sci. USA   112 , 10089–10092 (2015).

Kosslyn, S. M., Ganis, G. & Thompson, W. L. Neural foundations of imagery. Nat. Rev. Neurosci. 2 , 635–642 (2001).

Keogh, R. & Pearson, J. The perceptual and phenomenal capacity of mental imagery. Cognition 162 , 124–132 (2017).

Pearson, J., Clifford, C. W. G. & Tong, F. The functional impact of mental imagery on conscious perception. Curr. Biol. 18 , 982–986 (2008).

Brascamp, J. W., Knapen, T. H. J., Kanai, R., Van Ee, R. & Van Den Berg, A. V. Flash suppression and flash facilitation in binocular rivalry. J. Vis. 7 , 12 (2007).

Chang, S., Lewis, D. E. & Pearson, J. The functional effects of color perception and color imagery. J. Vis. 13 , 4–4 (2013).

Kosslyn, S. M. Scanning visual images: some structural implications. Percept. Psychophys. 14 , 90–94 (1973).

Kosslyn, S. M. Information representation in visual images. Cognit. Psychol. 7 , 341–370 (1975).

Kosslyn, S. M. Can imagery be distinguished from other forms of internal representation? Evidence from studies of information retrieval times. Mem. Cognit. 4 , 291–297 (1976).

Parsons, L. M. Imagined spatial transformations of one’s hands and feet. Cognit. Psychol. 19 , 178–241 (1987).

Shepard, R. N. & Metzler, J. Mental rotation of three-dimensional objects. Science 171 , 701–703 (1971).

Shepard, S. & Metzler, D. Mental rotation: effects of dimensionality of objects and type of task. J. Exp. Psychol. Hum. Percept. Perform. 14 , 3–11 (1988).

Kosslyn, S. M. & Pomerantz, J. R. Imagery, propositions, and the form of internal representations. Cognit. Psychol. 9 , 52–76 (1977).

Albers, A. M., Kok, P., Toni, I., Dijkerman, H. C. & de Lange, F. P. Shared representations for working memory and mental imagery in early visual cortex. Curr. Biol. 23 , 1427–1431 (2013).

Stokes, M., Thompson, R., Cusack, R. & Duncan, J. Top-down activation of shape-specific population codes in visual cortex during mental imagery. J. Neurosci. 29 , 1565–1572 (2009).

Harrison, S. A. & Tong, F. Decoding reveals the contents of visual working memory in early visual areas. Nature 458 , 632–635 (2009).

Kosslyn, S. M. et al. The role of area 17 in visual imagery: convergent evidence from PET and rTMS. Science 284 , 167–170 (1999).

Cui, X., Jeter, C. B., Yang, D., Montague, P. R. & Eagleman, D. M. Vividness of mental imagery: individual variability can be measured objectively. Vis. Res. 47 , 474–478 (2007).

Dijkstra, N., Zeidman, P., Ondobaka, S., van Gerven, M. A. J. & Friston, K. Distinct top-down and bottom-up brain connectivity during visual perception and imagery. Sci. Rep. 7 , 5677 (2017).

Bensafi, M., Rinck, F., Schaal, B. & Rouby, C. Verbal cues modulate hedonic perception of odors in 5-year-old children as well as in adults. Chem. Senses 32 , 855–862 (2007).

Djordjevic, J., Zatorre, R. J., Petrides, M., Boyle, J. A. & Jones-Gotman, M. Functional neuroimaging of odor imagery. NeuroImage 24 , 791–801 (2005).

Bunzeck, N., Wuestenberg, T., Lutz, K., Heinze, H. J. & Jancke, L. Scanning silence: mental imagery of complex sounds. NeuroImage 26 , 1119–1127 (2005).

Hubbard, T. L. Auditory imagery: empirical findings. Psychol. Bull. 136 , 302–329 (2010).

Schmidt, T. T., Ostwald, D. & Blankenburg, F. Imaging tactile imagery: changes in brain connectivity support perceptual grounding of mental images in primary sensory cortices. NeuroImage 98 , 216–224 (2014).

Schmidt, T. T. & Blankenburg, F. The somatotopy of mental tactile imagery. Front. Hum. Neurosci. 13 , 10 (2019).

Yoo, S.-S., Freeman, D. K., McCarthy, J. J. & Jolesz, F. A. Neural substrates of tactile imagery: a functional MRI study. NeuroReport 14 , 581–585 (2003).

Gerardin, E. Partially overlapping neural networks for real and imagined hand movements. Cereb. Cortex 10 , 1093–1104 (2000).

Hardwick, R. M., Caspers, S., Eickhoff, S. B. & Swinnen, S. P. Neural correlates of action: comparing meta-analyses of imagery, observation, and execution. Neurosci. Biobehav. Rev. 94 , 31–44 (2018).

Linke, A. C. & Cusack, R. Flexible information coding in human auditory cortex during perception, imagery, and STM of complex sounds. J. Cogn. Neurosci. 27 , 1322–1333 (2015).

Plailly, J., Delon-Martin, C. & Royet, J. P. Experience induces functional reorganization in brain regions involved in odor imagery in perfumers. Hum. Brain Mapp. 33 , 224–234 (2012).

Alemanno, F. et al. Action-related semantic content and negation polarity modulate motor areas during sentence reading: an event-related desynchronization study. Brain Res. 1484 , 39–49 (2012).

Bechtold, L., Ghio, M., Lange, J. & Bellebaum, C. Event-related desynchronization of mu and beta oscillations during the processing of novel tool names. Brain Lang. 177–178 , 44–55 (2018).

Moreno, I., de Vega, M. & León, I. Understanding action language modulates oscillatory mu and beta rhythms in the same way as observing actions. Brain Cogn. 82 , 236–242 (2013).

Moreno, I. et al. Brain dynamics in the comprehension of action-related language. a time-frequency analysis of mu rhythms. NeuroImage 109 , 50–62 (2015).

Niccolai, V. et al. Grasping hand verbs: oscillatory beta and alpha correlates of action-word processing. PLoS ONE 9 , e108059 (2014).

van Elk, M., van Schie, H. T., Zwaan, R. A. & Bekkering, H. The functional role of motor activation in language processing: motor cortical oscillations support lexical-semantic retrieval. NeuroImage 50 , 665–677 (2010).

Cayol, Z., Rotival, C., Paulignan, Y. & Nazir, T. A. “Embodied” language processing: mental motor imagery aptitude predicts word-definition skill for high but not for low imageable words in adolescents. Brain Cogn. 145 , 105628 (2020).

McKelvie, S. J. & Demers, E. G. Individual differences in reported visual imagery and memory performance. Br. J. Psychol. 70 , 51–57 (1979).

Bonnet, C. et al. Kinesthetic motor-imagery training improves performance on lexical-semantic access. PLoS ONE 17 , e0270352 (2022).

Pecher, D., van Dantzig, S. & Schifferstein, H. N. J. Concepts are not represented by conscious imagery. Psychon. Bull. Rev. 16 , 914–919 (2009).

Speed, L. J. & Majid, A. An exception to mental simulation: no evidence for embodied odor language. Cogn. Sci. 42 , 1146–1178 (2018).

Keogh, R., Pearson, J. & Zeman, A. in Handbook of Clinical Neurology vol. 178 (eds. Barton, J. J. S. & Leff, A.) 277–296 (Elsevier, 2021). This chapter provides a review of the extremes of visual imagery and current research on aphantasia and hyperphantasia.

Dance, C. J., Ipser, A. & Simner, J. The prevalence of aphantasia (imagery weakness) in the general population. Conscious. Cogn. 10 , 103243 (2022).

Zeman, A. et al. Phantasia — the psychological significance of lifelong visual imagery vividness extremes. Cortex 130 , 426–440 (2020).

Milton, F. et al. Behavioral and neural signatures of visual imagery vividness extremes: aphantasia versus hyperphantasia. Cereb. Cortex Commun. 2 , tgab035 (2021).

Farah, M. J., Hammond, K. M., Levine, D. N. & Calvanio, R. Visual and spatial mental imagery: dissociable systems of representation. Cognit. Psychol. 20 , 439–462 (1988).

Marks, D. F. Visual imagery differences in the recall of pictures. Br. J. Psychol. 64 , 17–24 (1973).

Dance, C. J., Ward, J. & Simner, J. What is the link between mental imagery and sensory sensitivity? Insights from aphantasia. Perception 50 , 757–782 (2021).

Dawes, A. J., Keogh, R., Andrillon, T. & Pearson, J. A cognitive profile of multi-sensory imagery, memory and dreaming in aphantasia. Sci. Rep. 10 , 10022 (2020).

Keogh, R. Visual working memory in aphantasia: retained accuracy and capacity with a different strategy. Cortex 143 , 237–253 (2021).

Wicken, M., Keogh, R. & Pearson, J. The critical role of mental imagery in human emotion: insights from fear-based imagery and aphantasia. Proc. R. Soc. B Biol. Sci. 288 , 20210267 (2021).

Bainbridge, W. A., Pounder, Z., Eardley, A. F. & Baker, C. I. Quantifying aphantasia through drawing: those without visual imagery show deficits in object but not spatial memory. Cortex 135 , 159–172 (2021).

Monzel, M., Keidel, K. & Reuter, M. Imagine, and you will find — lack of attentional guidance through visual imagery in aphantasics. Atten. Percept. Psychophys. 83 , 2486–2497 (2021).

Keogh, R. & Pearson, J. The blind mind: no sensory visual imagery in aphantasia. Cortex 105 , 53–60 (2018).

Kay, L., Keogh, R., Andrillon, T. & Pearson, J. The pupillary light response as a physiological index of aphantasia, sensory and phenomenological imagery strength. eLife 11 , e72484 (2022).

Visser, I. et al. Improving the generalizability of infant psychological research: the ManyBabies model. Behav. Brain Sci. 45 , e35 (2022).

Takahashi, J. et al. Diversity of aphantasia revealed by multiple assessments of visual imagery, multisensory imagery, and cognitive style. Front. Psychol. 14 , 1174873 (2023).

Blajenkova, O., Kozhevnikov, M. & Motes, M. A. Object-spatial imagery: a new self-report imagery questionnaire. Appl. Cogn. Psychol. 20 , 239–263 (2006).

Palermo, L., Boccia, M., Piccardi, L. & Nori, R. Congenital lack and extraordinary ability in object and spatial imagery: an investigation on sub-types of aphantasia and hyperphantasia. Conscious. Cogn. 103 , 103360 (2022).

Jacobs, C., Schwarzkopf, D. S. & Silvanto, J. Visual working memory performance in aphantasia. Cortex 105 , 61–73 (2018).

Monzel, M., Vetterlein, A. & Reuter, M. Memory deficits in aphantasics are not restricted to autobiographical memory — perspectives from the dual coding approach. J. Neuropsychol. 16 , 444–461 (2022).

Fulford, J. et al. The neural correlates of visual imagery vividness — an fMRI study and literature review. Cortex 105 , 26–40 (2018).

Speed, L. J. & Majid, A. Grounding language in the neglected senses of touch, taste, and smell. Cogn. Neuropsychol. 37 , 363–392 (2020).

Hald, L. A., van den Hurk, M. & Bekkering, H. Learning verbs more effectively through meaning congruent action animations. Learn. Instr. 39 , 107–122 (2015).

James, K. H. & Swain, S. N. Only self-generated actions create sensori-motor systems in the developing brain. Dev. Sci. 14 , 673–678 (2011).

Muraki, E. J., Siddiqui, I. A. & Pexman, P. M. Quantifying children’s sensorimotor experience: child body–object interaction ratings for 3359 English words. Behav. Res. Methods 54 , 2864–2877 (2022).

Thill, S. & Twomey, K. E. What’s on the inside counts: a grounded account of concept acquisition and development. Front. Psychol. 7 , 402 (2016).

Pexman, P. M. The role of embodiment in conceptual development. Lang. Cogn. Neurosci. 34 , 1274–1283 (2019).

Cortese, M. J. & Fugett, A. Imageability ratings for 3,000 monosyllabic words. Behav. Res. Methods Instrum. Comput. 36 , 384–387 (2004).

Schock, J., Cortese, M. J. & Khanna, M. M. Imageability estimates for 3,000 disyllabic words. Behav. Res. Methods 44 , 374–379 (2012).

Juhasz, B. J. & Yap, M. J. Sensory experience ratings for over 5,000 mono- and disyllabic words. Behav. Res. Methods 45 , 160–168 (2013).

Brysbaert, M. & New, B. Moving beyond Kucera and Francis: a critical evaluation of current word frequency norms and the introduction of a new and improved word frequency measure for American English. Behav. Res. Methods 41 , 977–990 (2009).

Hoffman, P., Lambon Ralph, M. A. & Rogers, T. T. Semantic diversity: a measure of semantic ambiguity based on variability in the contextual usage of words. Behav. Res. Methods 45 , 718–730 (2013).

Shaoul, C. & Westbury, C. Exploring lexical co-occurrence space using HiDEx. Behav. Res. Methods 42 , 393–413 (2010).

Pounder, Z. et al. Only minimal differences between individuals with congenital aphantasia and those with typical imagery on neuropsychological tasks that involve imagery. Cortex 148 , 180–192 (2022).

Dance, C. J. et al. What is the relationship between aphantasia, synaesthesia and autism? Conscious. Cogn. 89 , 103087 (2021).

Ganczarek, J., Żurawska-Żyła, R. & Rolek, A. “I remember things, but I can’t picture them.” What can a case of aphantasia tell us about imagery and memory? Psychiatr. Psychol. Klin. 20 , 134–141 (2020).

Keogh, R. & Pearson, J. Attention driven phantom vision: measuring the sensory strength of attentional templates and their relation to visual mental imagery and aphantasia. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. B Biol. Sci. 376 , 20190688 (2021).

Königsmark, V. T., Bergmann, J. & Reeder, R. R. The Ganzflicker experience: high probability of seeing vivid and complex pseudo-hallucinations with imagery but not aphantasia. Cortex 141 , 522–534 (2021).

Baron-Cohen, S., Wheelwright, S., Skinner, R., Martin, J. & Clubley, E. The Autism-spectrum Quotient (AQ): evidence from Asperger syndrome/high-functioning autism, males and females, scientists and mathematicians. J. Autism Dev. Disord. 31 , 5–17 (2001).

Blomkvist, A. Aphantasia: in search of a theory. Mind Lang . https://doi.org/10.1111/mila.12432 (2022).

Blazhenkova, O. & Pechenkova, E. The two eyes of the blind mind: object vs. spatial aphantasia? Russ. J. Cogn. Sci. 6 , 51–62 (2019).

Download references

Author information

Authors and affiliations.

Department of Psychology, University of Calgary, Calgary, Alberta, Canada

Emiko J. Muraki & Penny M. Pexman

Hotchkiss Brain Institute, University of Calgary, Calgary, Alberta, Canada

Centre for Language Studies, Radboud University, Nijmegen, The Netherlands

Laura J. Speed

You can also search for this author in PubMed   Google Scholar

Contributions

E.J.M. and P.M.P. conceptualized the paper. All authors contributed substantially to discussion of the content. E.J.M. wrote the article. All authors reviewed and/or edited the manuscript before submission.

Corresponding authors

Correspondence to Emiko J. Muraki or Penny M. Pexman .

Ethics declarations

Competing interests.

The authors declare no competing interests.

Peer review

Peer review information.

Nature Reviews Psychology thanks Laura Bechtold, Leo Dutriaux and Jamie Ward for their contribution to the peer review of this work.

Additional information

Publisher’s note Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article.

Muraki, E.J., Speed, L.J. & Pexman, P.M. Insights into embodied cognition and mental imagery from aphantasia. Nat Rev Psychol 2 , 591–605 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1038/s44159-023-00221-9

Download citation

Accepted : 17 July 2023

Published : 22 August 2023

Issue Date : October 2023

DOI : https://doi.org/10.1038/s44159-023-00221-9

Share this article

Anyone you share the following link with will be able to read this content:

Sorry, a shareable link is not currently available for this article.

Provided by the Springer Nature SharedIt content-sharing initiative

Quick links

  • Explore articles by subject
  • Guide to authors
  • Editorial policies

Sign up for the Nature Briefing newsletter — what matters in science, free to your inbox daily.

mental representation

Mental Representations and Their Analysis: An Epistemological Perspective

  • First Online: 31 December 2009

Cite this chapter

mental representation

  • J. Michael Spector 4  

870 Accesses

11 Citations

It is widely accepted that mental representations (e.g., mental models and other internal cognitive structures) play a key role in the development of knowledge and expertise. This is especially true in problem-solving domains that involve many interacting components (e.g., complex dynamic systems). However, mental representations are not directly observable. In order to help improve understanding (knowledge and performance) in these domains, it is useful to have a good sense of how an individual is thinking about the problem situation. More specifically, understanding mental model development and formation can improve learning and instruction. Meaningful formative feedback often depends on the ability to identify faulty or incomplete or inappropriate internal representations of one or more aspects of the problem situation. In order to provide such feedback in a timely manner, it is necessary to have methods and tools that reliably reveal a learner’s relevant mental representations. Such methods and tools used to assess mental models are the primary focus in this volume. In this chapter, the focus is on the epistemological status of mental models and their analysis. The specific questions addressed herein are as follows: (a) What can we know about mental representations? (b) Can mental models be reliably assessed? and, (c) How useful are mental model measures in facilitating the development of knowledge and expertise? These are large questions that are not likely to have complete and definitive answers in the near future. The discussion in this chapter should be regarded only as a modest attempt to encourage further dialogue and investigation.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save.

  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or Ebook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
  • Durable hardcover edition

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

mental representation

Model-Based Learning and Performance

Do knowledge-component models need to incorporate representational competencies.

mental representation

Twenty Years on: Reflections on “Supporting the Use of External Representations in Problem Solving”…

Anderson, J. L. (2007). How can the human mind occur in the physical world ? New York: Oxford University Press.

Google Scholar  

Bloom, B. S. (Ed.). (1956). Taxonomy of educational objectives, Handbook 1: The cognitive domain . New York: McKay.

Bransford, J. D., Brown, A. L., & Cocking, R. R. (Eds.). (2000). How people learn: Brain, mind, experience, and school . Washington, DC: National Academy Press.

Cronbach, L. J., & Meehl, P. E. (1955). Construct validity in psychological tests. Psychological Bulletin, 52 , 281–302.

Article   Google Scholar  

Dreyfus, H. L., & Dreyfus, S. E. (1986). Mind over machine: The power of human intuition and expertise in the era of the computer . New York: Free Press.

Ericsson, K. A. (2001). Attaining excellence through deliberate practice: Insights from the study of expert performance. In M. Ferrari (Ed.), The pursuit of excellence in education (pp. 21–55). Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.

Ericsson, K. A., & Simon, H. A. (1993). Protocol analysis: Verbal reports as data (Rev. ed.). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Ericsson, K. A., & Smith, J. (1991). Prospects and limits in the empirical study of expertise: An introduction. In K. A. Ericsson & J. Smith (Eds.), Toward a general theory of expertise: Prospects and limits (pp. 1–38). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Gagné, R. M. (1985). The conditions of learning (4th ed.). New York: Holt, Rinehart, and Winston.

Gagné, R. M., & Merrill, M. D. (1990). Integrative goals for instructional design. Educational Technology Research and Development, 38 (1), 23–40.

Ifenthaler, D. (2007, October). Relational, structural, and semantic analysis of graphical representations and concept maps. Introducing the SMD-technology . Paper presented at the Annual Meeting of the Association for Educational Communications and Technology, Anaheim, CA.

Johnson-Laird, P. N. (1983). Mental models . Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Jonassen, D. H. (2000). Toward a design theory of problem solving. Educational Technology Research & Development, 48 , 63–85.

Klein, G. A., Orsanu, J., Calderwood, R., & Zsambok, C. E. (1993). Decision making in action: Models and methods . Norwood, NJ: Ablex.

Kim, H. (2008). An investigation of the effects of model-centered instruction in individual and collaborative contexts: The case of acquiring instructional design expertise . Unpublished dissertation, Florida State University, Tallahassee, FL.

Lee, J. (2008). Effects of model-centered instruction and levels of expertise on ill-structured problem solving . Unpublished dissertation, Florida State University, Tallahassee, FL.

McKeown, J. (2008). Using annotated concept map assessments as predictors of performance and understanding of complex problems for teacher technology integration . Unpublished dissertation, Florida State University, Tallahassee, FL.

Merrill, M. D. (1993). An integrated model for automating instructional design and delivery. In J. M. Spector, M. C. Polson, & D. J. Muraida (Eds.), Automating instructional design: Concepts and issues (pp. 147–190). Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Educational Technology.

Olson, S., & Loucks-Horsley, S. (2000). Inquiry and the national science education standards: A guide for teaching and learning . Washington, DC: National Academies Press.

Pirnay-Dummer, P. (2007, April). Model inspection trace of concepts and relations. A heuristic approach to language-oriented model assessment . Paper presented at the annual meeting of the American Educational Research Association, Chicago, IL.

Pirnay-Dummer, P., Ifenthaler, D., & Spector, J. M. (2009). Highly integrated model assessment technology and tools. Educational Technology Research and Development , 57 (6).

Rittel, H., & Webber, M. (1973). Dilemmas in a general theory of planning. Policy Sciences, 4 , 155–169.

Seel, N. M. (2001). Epistemology, situated cognition, and mental models: “Like a bridge over troubled water”. Instructional Science , 29 (4–5), 403–427.

Spector, J. M. (2004). Current issues in new learning. In K. Morgan, C. A. Brebbia, J. Sanchez, & A. Voiskounsky (Eds.), Human perspectives in the Internet society: Culture, psychology and gender (pp. 429–440). Southampton, UK: WIT Press.

Spector, J. M. (2006). Introduction to the special issue on models, simulations and learning in complex domains. Technology, Instruction, Cognition and Learning, 3 (3–4), 199–204.

Spector, J. M., & Koszalka, T. A. (2004). The DEEP methodology for assessing learning incomplex domains (Final report to the National Science Foundation Evaluative Research and Evaluation Capacity Building). Syracuse, NY: Syracuse University.

Spector, J. M., & Merrill, M. D. (2008). Editorial: Effective, efficient and engaging (E 3 ) learning in the digital age. Distance Education, 29 (2), 123–126.

Taricani, E. M., & Clariana, R. B. (2006). A technique for automatically scoring open-ended concept maps. Eduational Technology Research and Development, 54 (1), 65–82.

van Merriënboer, J. J. G., & Dijkstra, S. (1997). The four-component instructional-design model for training complex cognitive skills. In R. D. Tennyson, F. Schott, N. Seel, & S. Dijkstra (Eds.), Instructional design: International perspectives (Vol. 1, pp. 427–446). Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.

van Merriënboer, J. J. G., & Kirschner, P. A. (2007). Ten steps to complex learning . Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.

Wittgenstein, L. (1922). Tractatus logico-philosophicus (C. K. Ogden Trans.). London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

Wittgenstein, L. (1953). Philosophical investigations . London: Blackwell.

Download references

Author information

Authors and affiliations.

Learning and Performance Support Laboratory, University of Georgia, Athens, GA, USA

J. Michael Spector

You can also search for this author in PubMed   Google Scholar

Corresponding author

Correspondence to J. Michael Spector .

Editor information

Editors and affiliations.

Abt. Lernforschung, Universität Freiburg, Rempartstr. 11, Freiburg, 79085, Germany

Dirk Ifenthaler

Pablo Pirnay-Dummer

Inst. Erziehungswissenschaft, Univ. Freiburg, Freiburg, 79085, Germany

Norbert M. Seel

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2010 Springer Science+Business Media, LLC

About this chapter

Spector, J.M. (2010). Mental Representations and Their Analysis: An Epistemological Perspective. In: Ifenthaler, D., Pirnay-Dummer, P., Seel, N. (eds) Computer-Based Diagnostics and Systematic Analysis of Knowledge. Springer, Boston, MA. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4419-5662-0_3

Download citation

DOI : https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4419-5662-0_3

Published : 31 December 2009

Publisher Name : Springer, Boston, MA

Print ISBN : 978-1-4419-5661-3

Online ISBN : 978-1-4419-5662-0

eBook Packages : Humanities, Social Sciences and Law Education (R0)

Share this chapter

Anyone you share the following link with will be able to read this content:

Sorry, a shareable link is not currently available for this article.

Provided by the Springer Nature SharedIt content-sharing initiative

  • Publish with us

Policies and ethics

  • Find a journal
  • Track your research

Kevin Leo Yabut Nadal, Ph.D.

Why Representation Matters and Why It’s Still Not Enough

Reflections on growing up brown, queer, and asian american..

Posted December 27, 2021 | Reviewed by Ekua Hagan

  • Positive media representation can be helpful in increasing self-esteem for people of marginalized groups (especially youth).
  • Interpersonal contact and exposure through media representation can assist in reducing stereotypes of underrepresented groups.
  • Representation in educational curricula and social media can provide validation and support, especially for youth of marginalized groups.

Growing up as a Brown Asian American child of immigrants, I never really saw anyone who looked like me in the media. The TV shows and movies I watched mostly concentrated on blonde-haired, white, or light-skinned protagonists. They also normalized western and heterosexist ideals and behaviors, while hardly ever depicting things that reflected my everyday life. For example, it was equally odd and fascinating that people on TV didn’t eat rice at every meal; that their parents didn’t speak with accents; or that no one seemed to navigate a world of daily microaggressions . Despite these observations, I continued to absorb this mass media—internalizing messages of what my life should be like or what I should aspire to be like.

Ron Gejon, used with permission

Because there were so few media images of people who looked like me, I distinctly remember the joy and validation that emerged when I did see those representations. Filipino American actors like Ernie Reyes, Nia Peeples, Dante Basco, and Tia Carrere looked like they could be my cousins. Each time they sporadically appeared in films and television series throughout my youth, their mere presence brought a sense of pride. However, because they never played Filipino characters (e.g., Carrere was Chinese American in Wayne's World ) or their racial identities remained unaddressed (e.g., Basco as Rufio in Hook ), I did not know for certain that they were Filipino American like me. And because the internet was not readily accessible (nor fully informational) until my late adolescence , I could not easily find out.

Through my Ethnic Studies classes as an undergraduate student (and my later research on Asian American and Filipino American experiences with microaggressions), I discovered that my perspectives were not that unique. Many Asian Americans and other people of color often struggle with their racial and ethnic identity development —with many citing how a lack of media representation negatively impacts their self-esteem and overall views of their racial or cultural groups. Scholars and community leaders have declared mottos like how it's "hard to be what you can’t see," asserting that people from marginalized groups do not pursue career or academic opportunities when they are not exposed to such possibilities. For example, when women (and women of color specifically) don’t see themselves represented in STEM fields , they may internalize that such careers are not made for them. When people of color don’t see themselves in the arts or in government positions, they likely learn similar messages too.

Complicating these messages are my intersectional identities as a queer person of color. In my teens, it was heartbreakingly lonely to witness everyday homophobia (especially unnecessary homophobic language) in almost all television programming. The few visual examples I saw of anyone LGBTQ involved mostly white, gay, cisgender people. While there was some comfort in seeing them navigate their coming out processes or overcome heterosexism on screen, their storylines often appeared unrealistic—at least in comparison to the nuanced homophobia I observed in my religious, immigrant family. In some ways, not seeing LGBTQ people of color in the media kept me in the closet for years.

How representation can help

Representation can serve as opportunities for minoritized people to find community support and validation. For example, recent studies have found that social media has given LGBTQ young people the outlets to connect with others—especially when the COVID-19 pandemic has limited in-person opportunities. Given the increased suicidal ideation, depression , and other mental health issues among LGBTQ youth amidst this global pandemic, visibility via social media can possibly save lives. Relatedly, taking Ethnic Studies courses can be valuable in helping students to develop a critical consciousness that is culturally relevant to their lives. In this way, representation can allow students of color to personally connect to school, potentially making their educational pursuits more meaningful.

Further, representation can be helpful in reducing negative stereotypes about other groups. Initially discussed by psychologist Dr. Gordon Allport as Intergroup Contact Theory, researchers believed that the more exposure or contact that people had to groups who were different from them, the less likely they would maintain prejudice . Literature has supported how positive LGBTQ media representation helped transform public opinions about LGBTQ people and their rights. In 2019, the Pew Research Center reported that the general US population significantly changed their views of same-sex marriage in just 15 years—with 60% of the population being opposed in 2004 to 61% in favor in 2019. While there are many other factors that likely influenced these perspective shifts, studies suggest that positive LGBTQ media depictions played a significant role.

For Asian Americans and other groups who have been historically underrepresented in the media, any visibility can feel like a win. For example, Gold House recently featured an article in Vanity Fair , highlighting the power of Asian American visibility in the media—citing blockbuster films like Crazy Rich Asians and Shang-Chi and the Legend of the Ten Rings . Asian American producers like Mindy Kaling of Never Have I Ever and The Sex Lives of College Girls demonstrate how influential creators of color can initiate their own projects and write their own storylines, in order to directly increase representation (and indirectly increase mental health and positive esteem for its audiences of color).

When representation is not enough

However, representation simply is not enough—especially when it is one-dimensional, superficial, or not actually representative. Some scholars describe how Asian American media depictions still tend to reinforce stereotypes, which may negatively impact identity development for Asian American youth. Asian American Studies is still needed to teach about oppression and to combat hate violence. Further, representation might also fail to reflect the true diversity of communities; historically, Brown Asian Americans have been underrepresented in Asian American media, resulting in marginalization within marginalized groups. For example, Filipino Americans—despite being the first Asian American group to settle in the US and one of the largest immigrant groups—remain underrepresented across many sectors, including academia, arts, and government.

Representation should never be the final goal; instead, it should merely be one step toward equity. Having a diverse cast on a television show is meaningless if those storylines promote harmful stereotypes or fail to address societal inequities. Being the “first” at anything is pointless if there aren’t efforts to address the systemic obstacles that prevent people from certain groups from succeeding in the first place.

mental representation

Instead, representation should be intentional. People in power should aim for their content to reflect their audiences—especially if they know that doing so could assist in increasing people's self-esteem and wellness. People who have the opportunity to represent their identity groups in any sector may make conscious efforts to use their influence to teach (or remind) others that their communities exist. Finally, parents and teachers can be more intentional in ensuring that their children and students always feel seen and validated. By providing youth with visual representations of people they can relate to, they can potentially save future generations from a lifetime of feeling underrepresented or misunderstood.

Kevin Leo Yabut Nadal, Ph.D.

Kevin Leo Yabut Nadal, Ph.D., is a Distinguished Professor of Psychology at the City University of New York and the author of books including Microaggressions and Traumatic Stress .

  • Find a Therapist
  • Find a Treatment Center
  • Find a Psychiatrist
  • Find a Support Group
  • Find Online Therapy
  • United States
  • Brooklyn, NY
  • Chicago, IL
  • Houston, TX
  • Los Angeles, CA
  • New York, NY
  • Portland, OR
  • San Diego, CA
  • San Francisco, CA
  • Seattle, WA
  • Washington, DC
  • Asperger's
  • Bipolar Disorder
  • Chronic Pain
  • Eating Disorders
  • Passive Aggression
  • Personality
  • Goal Setting
  • Positive Psychology
  • Stopping Smoking
  • Low Sexual Desire
  • Relationships
  • Child Development
  • Self Tests NEW
  • Therapy Center
  • Diagnosis Dictionary
  • Types of Therapy

July 2024 magazine cover

Sticking up for yourself is no easy task. But there are concrete skills you can use to hone your assertiveness and advocate for yourself.

  • Emotional Intelligence
  • Gaslighting
  • Affective Forecasting
  • Neuroscience

X

Centre for Behaviour Change

  • Consultancy
  • CBC Conference
  • Related Organisations

Menu

New paper on Young People's Involvement and Under-Representation in Mental Health Research

2 July 2024

This paper provides a practical resource for researchers considering involving young people in the research process, and suggests what data should be collected to improve reporting on the diversity of the young people involved.

Workshop with young people

Full title:  Understanding and Defining Young People's Involvementand Under‐Representation in Mental Health Research: A Delphi Study

Authors:  Rachel Perowne , Sarah Rowe , Leslie Gutman

The mental health of young people (aged 16–25 years) is a growing public health concern in the UnitedKingdom due to the increasing numbers of young people experiencing mental health difficulties, with many not in contact withmental health services. To design services that meet the needs of all young people, a diversity of young people must be involvedin mental health research, beyond being participants. This Delphi study generated an agreed‐upon definition of under‐representation, an identification of when in the research process there is under‐representation and the characteristics of the young people who are under‐represented. Experts further agreed on demographicdata that should be collected to improve reporting on involvement.

Read the paper  

Related News

  • Search Menu

Sign in through your institution

  • Browse content in Arts and Humanities
  • Browse content in Archaeology
  • Anglo-Saxon and Medieval Archaeology
  • Archaeological Methodology and Techniques
  • Archaeology by Region
  • Archaeology of Religion
  • Archaeology of Trade and Exchange
  • Biblical Archaeology
  • Contemporary and Public Archaeology
  • Environmental Archaeology
  • Historical Archaeology
  • History and Theory of Archaeology
  • Industrial Archaeology
  • Landscape Archaeology
  • Mortuary Archaeology
  • Prehistoric Archaeology
  • Underwater Archaeology
  • Urban Archaeology
  • Zooarchaeology
  • Browse content in Architecture
  • Architectural Structure and Design
  • History of Architecture
  • Residential and Domestic Buildings
  • Theory of Architecture
  • Browse content in Art
  • Art Subjects and Themes
  • History of Art
  • Industrial and Commercial Art
  • Theory of Art
  • Biographical Studies
  • Byzantine Studies
  • Browse content in Classical Studies
  • Classical History
  • Classical Philosophy
  • Classical Mythology
  • Classical Literature
  • Classical Reception
  • Classical Art and Architecture
  • Classical Oratory and Rhetoric
  • Greek and Roman Papyrology
  • Greek and Roman Epigraphy
  • Greek and Roman Law
  • Greek and Roman Archaeology
  • Late Antiquity
  • Religion in the Ancient World
  • Social History
  • Digital Humanities
  • Browse content in History
  • Colonialism and Imperialism
  • Diplomatic History
  • Environmental History
  • Genealogy, Heraldry, Names, and Honours
  • Genocide and Ethnic Cleansing
  • Historical Geography
  • History by Period
  • History of Emotions
  • History of Agriculture
  • History of Education
  • History of Gender and Sexuality
  • Industrial History
  • Intellectual History
  • International History
  • Labour History
  • Legal and Constitutional History
  • Local and Family History
  • Maritime History
  • Military History
  • National Liberation and Post-Colonialism
  • Oral History
  • Political History
  • Public History
  • Regional and National History
  • Revolutions and Rebellions
  • Slavery and Abolition of Slavery
  • Social and Cultural History
  • Theory, Methods, and Historiography
  • Urban History
  • World History
  • Browse content in Language Teaching and Learning
  • Language Learning (Specific Skills)
  • Language Teaching Theory and Methods
  • Browse content in Linguistics
  • Applied Linguistics
  • Cognitive Linguistics
  • Computational Linguistics
  • Forensic Linguistics
  • Grammar, Syntax and Morphology
  • Historical and Diachronic Linguistics
  • History of English
  • Language Evolution
  • Language Reference
  • Language Acquisition
  • Language Variation
  • Language Families
  • Lexicography
  • Linguistic Anthropology
  • Linguistic Theories
  • Linguistic Typology
  • Phonetics and Phonology
  • Psycholinguistics
  • Sociolinguistics
  • Translation and Interpretation
  • Writing Systems
  • Browse content in Literature
  • Bibliography
  • Children's Literature Studies
  • Literary Studies (Romanticism)
  • Literary Studies (American)
  • Literary Studies (Asian)
  • Literary Studies (European)
  • Literary Studies (Eco-criticism)
  • Literary Studies (Modernism)
  • Literary Studies - World
  • Literary Studies (1500 to 1800)
  • Literary Studies (19th Century)
  • Literary Studies (20th Century onwards)
  • Literary Studies (African American Literature)
  • Literary Studies (British and Irish)
  • Literary Studies (Early and Medieval)
  • Literary Studies (Fiction, Novelists, and Prose Writers)
  • Literary Studies (Gender Studies)
  • Literary Studies (Graphic Novels)
  • Literary Studies (History of the Book)
  • Literary Studies (Plays and Playwrights)
  • Literary Studies (Poetry and Poets)
  • Literary Studies (Postcolonial Literature)
  • Literary Studies (Queer Studies)
  • Literary Studies (Science Fiction)
  • Literary Studies (Travel Literature)
  • Literary Studies (War Literature)
  • Literary Studies (Women's Writing)
  • Literary Theory and Cultural Studies
  • Mythology and Folklore
  • Shakespeare Studies and Criticism
  • Browse content in Media Studies
  • Browse content in Music
  • Applied Music
  • Dance and Music
  • Ethics in Music
  • Ethnomusicology
  • Gender and Sexuality in Music
  • Medicine and Music
  • Music Cultures
  • Music and Media
  • Music and Religion
  • Music and Culture
  • Music Education and Pedagogy
  • Music Theory and Analysis
  • Musical Scores, Lyrics, and Libretti
  • Musical Structures, Styles, and Techniques
  • Musicology and Music History
  • Performance Practice and Studies
  • Race and Ethnicity in Music
  • Sound Studies
  • Browse content in Performing Arts
  • Browse content in Philosophy
  • Aesthetics and Philosophy of Art
  • Epistemology
  • Feminist Philosophy
  • History of Western Philosophy
  • Metaphysics
  • Moral Philosophy
  • Non-Western Philosophy
  • Philosophy of Language
  • Philosophy of Mind
  • Philosophy of Perception
  • Philosophy of Science
  • Philosophy of Action
  • Philosophy of Law
  • Philosophy of Religion
  • Philosophy of Mathematics and Logic
  • Practical Ethics
  • Social and Political Philosophy
  • Browse content in Religion
  • Biblical Studies
  • Christianity
  • East Asian Religions
  • History of Religion
  • Judaism and Jewish Studies
  • Qumran Studies
  • Religion and Education
  • Religion and Health
  • Religion and Politics
  • Religion and Science
  • Religion and Law
  • Religion and Art, Literature, and Music
  • Religious Studies
  • Browse content in Society and Culture
  • Cookery, Food, and Drink
  • Cultural Studies
  • Customs and Traditions
  • Ethical Issues and Debates
  • Hobbies, Games, Arts and Crafts
  • Natural world, Country Life, and Pets
  • Popular Beliefs and Controversial Knowledge
  • Sports and Outdoor Recreation
  • Technology and Society
  • Travel and Holiday
  • Visual Culture
  • Browse content in Law
  • Arbitration
  • Browse content in Company and Commercial Law
  • Commercial Law
  • Company Law
  • Browse content in Comparative Law
  • Systems of Law
  • Competition Law
  • Browse content in Constitutional and Administrative Law
  • Government Powers
  • Judicial Review
  • Local Government Law
  • Military and Defence Law
  • Parliamentary and Legislative Practice
  • Construction Law
  • Contract Law
  • Browse content in Criminal Law
  • Criminal Procedure
  • Criminal Evidence Law
  • Sentencing and Punishment
  • Employment and Labour Law
  • Environment and Energy Law
  • Browse content in Financial Law
  • Banking Law
  • Insolvency Law
  • History of Law
  • Human Rights and Immigration
  • Intellectual Property Law
  • Browse content in International Law
  • Private International Law and Conflict of Laws
  • Public International Law
  • IT and Communications Law
  • Jurisprudence and Philosophy of Law
  • Law and Politics
  • Law and Society
  • Browse content in Legal System and Practice
  • Courts and Procedure
  • Legal Skills and Practice
  • Primary Sources of Law
  • Regulation of Legal Profession
  • Medical and Healthcare Law
  • Browse content in Policing
  • Criminal Investigation and Detection
  • Police and Security Services
  • Police Procedure and Law
  • Police Regional Planning
  • Browse content in Property Law
  • Personal Property Law
  • Study and Revision
  • Terrorism and National Security Law
  • Browse content in Trusts Law
  • Wills and Probate or Succession
  • Browse content in Medicine and Health
  • Browse content in Allied Health Professions
  • Arts Therapies
  • Clinical Science
  • Dietetics and Nutrition
  • Occupational Therapy
  • Operating Department Practice
  • Physiotherapy
  • Radiography
  • Speech and Language Therapy
  • Browse content in Anaesthetics
  • General Anaesthesia
  • Neuroanaesthesia
  • Clinical Neuroscience
  • Browse content in Clinical Medicine
  • Acute Medicine
  • Cardiovascular Medicine
  • Clinical Genetics
  • Clinical Pharmacology and Therapeutics
  • Dermatology
  • Endocrinology and Diabetes
  • Gastroenterology
  • Genito-urinary Medicine
  • Geriatric Medicine
  • Infectious Diseases
  • Medical Toxicology
  • Medical Oncology
  • Pain Medicine
  • Palliative Medicine
  • Rehabilitation Medicine
  • Respiratory Medicine and Pulmonology
  • Rheumatology
  • Sleep Medicine
  • Sports and Exercise Medicine
  • Community Medical Services
  • Critical Care
  • Emergency Medicine
  • Forensic Medicine
  • Haematology
  • History of Medicine
  • Browse content in Medical Skills
  • Clinical Skills
  • Communication Skills
  • Nursing Skills
  • Surgical Skills
  • Browse content in Medical Dentistry
  • Oral and Maxillofacial Surgery
  • Paediatric Dentistry
  • Restorative Dentistry and Orthodontics
  • Surgical Dentistry
  • Medical Ethics
  • Medical Statistics and Methodology
  • Browse content in Neurology
  • Clinical Neurophysiology
  • Neuropathology
  • Nursing Studies
  • Browse content in Obstetrics and Gynaecology
  • Gynaecology
  • Occupational Medicine
  • Ophthalmology
  • Otolaryngology (ENT)
  • Browse content in Paediatrics
  • Neonatology
  • Browse content in Pathology
  • Chemical Pathology
  • Clinical Cytogenetics and Molecular Genetics
  • Histopathology
  • Medical Microbiology and Virology
  • Patient Education and Information
  • Browse content in Pharmacology
  • Psychopharmacology
  • Browse content in Popular Health
  • Caring for Others
  • Complementary and Alternative Medicine
  • Self-help and Personal Development
  • Browse content in Preclinical Medicine
  • Cell Biology
  • Molecular Biology and Genetics
  • Reproduction, Growth and Development
  • Primary Care
  • Professional Development in Medicine
  • Browse content in Psychiatry
  • Addiction Medicine
  • Child and Adolescent Psychiatry
  • Forensic Psychiatry
  • Learning Disabilities
  • Old Age Psychiatry
  • Psychotherapy
  • Browse content in Public Health and Epidemiology
  • Epidemiology
  • Public Health
  • Browse content in Radiology
  • Clinical Radiology
  • Interventional Radiology
  • Nuclear Medicine
  • Radiation Oncology
  • Reproductive Medicine
  • Browse content in Surgery
  • Cardiothoracic Surgery
  • Gastro-intestinal and Colorectal Surgery
  • General Surgery
  • Neurosurgery
  • Paediatric Surgery
  • Peri-operative Care
  • Plastic and Reconstructive Surgery
  • Surgical Oncology
  • Transplant Surgery
  • Trauma and Orthopaedic Surgery
  • Vascular Surgery
  • Browse content in Science and Mathematics
  • Browse content in Biological Sciences
  • Aquatic Biology
  • Biochemistry
  • Bioinformatics and Computational Biology
  • Developmental Biology
  • Ecology and Conservation
  • Evolutionary Biology
  • Genetics and Genomics
  • Microbiology
  • Molecular and Cell Biology
  • Natural History
  • Plant Sciences and Forestry
  • Research Methods in Life Sciences
  • Structural Biology
  • Systems Biology
  • Zoology and Animal Sciences
  • Browse content in Chemistry
  • Analytical Chemistry
  • Computational Chemistry
  • Crystallography
  • Environmental Chemistry
  • Industrial Chemistry
  • Inorganic Chemistry
  • Materials Chemistry
  • Medicinal Chemistry
  • Mineralogy and Gems
  • Organic Chemistry
  • Physical Chemistry
  • Polymer Chemistry
  • Study and Communication Skills in Chemistry
  • Theoretical Chemistry
  • Browse content in Computer Science
  • Artificial Intelligence
  • Computer Architecture and Logic Design
  • Game Studies
  • Human-Computer Interaction
  • Mathematical Theory of Computation
  • Programming Languages
  • Software Engineering
  • Systems Analysis and Design
  • Virtual Reality
  • Browse content in Computing
  • Business Applications
  • Computer Security
  • Computer Games
  • Computer Networking and Communications
  • Digital Lifestyle
  • Graphical and Digital Media Applications
  • Operating Systems
  • Browse content in Earth Sciences and Geography
  • Atmospheric Sciences
  • Environmental Geography
  • Geology and the Lithosphere
  • Maps and Map-making
  • Meteorology and Climatology
  • Oceanography and Hydrology
  • Palaeontology
  • Physical Geography and Topography
  • Regional Geography
  • Soil Science
  • Urban Geography
  • Browse content in Engineering and Technology
  • Agriculture and Farming
  • Biological Engineering
  • Civil Engineering, Surveying, and Building
  • Electronics and Communications Engineering
  • Energy Technology
  • Engineering (General)
  • Environmental Science, Engineering, and Technology
  • History of Engineering and Technology
  • Mechanical Engineering and Materials
  • Technology of Industrial Chemistry
  • Transport Technology and Trades
  • Browse content in Environmental Science
  • Applied Ecology (Environmental Science)
  • Conservation of the Environment (Environmental Science)
  • Environmental Sustainability
  • Environmentalist Thought and Ideology (Environmental Science)
  • Management of Land and Natural Resources (Environmental Science)
  • Natural Disasters (Environmental Science)
  • Nuclear Issues (Environmental Science)
  • Pollution and Threats to the Environment (Environmental Science)
  • Social Impact of Environmental Issues (Environmental Science)
  • History of Science and Technology
  • Browse content in Materials Science
  • Ceramics and Glasses
  • Composite Materials
  • Metals, Alloying, and Corrosion
  • Nanotechnology
  • Browse content in Mathematics
  • Applied Mathematics
  • Biomathematics and Statistics
  • History of Mathematics
  • Mathematical Education
  • Mathematical Finance
  • Mathematical Analysis
  • Numerical and Computational Mathematics
  • Probability and Statistics
  • Pure Mathematics
  • Browse content in Neuroscience
  • Cognition and Behavioural Neuroscience
  • Development of the Nervous System
  • Disorders of the Nervous System
  • History of Neuroscience
  • Invertebrate Neurobiology
  • Molecular and Cellular Systems
  • Neuroendocrinology and Autonomic Nervous System
  • Neuroscientific Techniques
  • Sensory and Motor Systems
  • Browse content in Physics
  • Astronomy and Astrophysics
  • Atomic, Molecular, and Optical Physics
  • Biological and Medical Physics
  • Classical Mechanics
  • Computational Physics
  • Condensed Matter Physics
  • Electromagnetism, Optics, and Acoustics
  • History of Physics
  • Mathematical and Statistical Physics
  • Measurement Science
  • Nuclear Physics
  • Particles and Fields
  • Plasma Physics
  • Quantum Physics
  • Relativity and Gravitation
  • Semiconductor and Mesoscopic Physics
  • Browse content in Psychology
  • Affective Sciences
  • Clinical Psychology
  • Cognitive Psychology
  • Cognitive Neuroscience
  • Criminal and Forensic Psychology
  • Developmental Psychology
  • Educational Psychology
  • Evolutionary Psychology
  • Health Psychology
  • History and Systems in Psychology
  • Music Psychology
  • Neuropsychology
  • Organizational Psychology
  • Psychological Assessment and Testing
  • Psychology of Human-Technology Interaction
  • Psychology Professional Development and Training
  • Research Methods in Psychology
  • Social Psychology
  • Browse content in Social Sciences
  • Browse content in Anthropology
  • Anthropology of Religion
  • Human Evolution
  • Medical Anthropology
  • Physical Anthropology
  • Regional Anthropology
  • Social and Cultural Anthropology
  • Theory and Practice of Anthropology
  • Browse content in Business and Management
  • Business Ethics
  • Business Strategy
  • Business History
  • Business and Technology
  • Business and Government
  • Business and the Environment
  • Comparative Management
  • Corporate Governance
  • Corporate Social Responsibility
  • Entrepreneurship
  • Health Management
  • Human Resource Management
  • Industrial and Employment Relations
  • Industry Studies
  • Information and Communication Technologies
  • International Business
  • Knowledge Management
  • Management and Management Techniques
  • Operations Management
  • Organizational Theory and Behaviour
  • Pensions and Pension Management
  • Public and Nonprofit Management
  • Strategic Management
  • Supply Chain Management
  • Browse content in Criminology and Criminal Justice
  • Criminal Justice
  • Criminology
  • Forms of Crime
  • International and Comparative Criminology
  • Youth Violence and Juvenile Justice
  • Development Studies
  • Browse content in Economics
  • Agricultural, Environmental, and Natural Resource Economics
  • Asian Economics
  • Behavioural Finance
  • Behavioural Economics and Neuroeconomics
  • Econometrics and Mathematical Economics
  • Economic History
  • Economic Systems
  • Economic Methodology
  • Economic Development and Growth
  • Financial Markets
  • Financial Institutions and Services
  • General Economics and Teaching
  • Health, Education, and Welfare
  • History of Economic Thought
  • International Economics
  • Labour and Demographic Economics
  • Law and Economics
  • Macroeconomics and Monetary Economics
  • Microeconomics
  • Public Economics
  • Urban, Rural, and Regional Economics
  • Welfare Economics
  • Browse content in Education
  • Adult Education and Continuous Learning
  • Care and Counselling of Students
  • Early Childhood and Elementary Education
  • Educational Equipment and Technology
  • Educational Strategies and Policy
  • Higher and Further Education
  • Organization and Management of Education
  • Philosophy and Theory of Education
  • Schools Studies
  • Secondary Education
  • Teaching of a Specific Subject
  • Teaching of Specific Groups and Special Educational Needs
  • Teaching Skills and Techniques
  • Browse content in Environment
  • Applied Ecology (Social Science)
  • Climate Change
  • Conservation of the Environment (Social Science)
  • Environmentalist Thought and Ideology (Social Science)
  • Management of Land and Natural Resources (Social Science)
  • Natural Disasters (Environment)
  • Social Impact of Environmental Issues (Social Science)
  • Sustainability
  • Browse content in Human Geography
  • Cultural Geography
  • Economic Geography
  • Political Geography
  • Browse content in Interdisciplinary Studies
  • Communication Studies
  • Museums, Libraries, and Information Sciences
  • Browse content in Politics
  • African Politics
  • Asian Politics
  • Chinese Politics
  • Comparative Politics
  • Conflict Politics
  • Elections and Electoral Studies
  • Environmental Politics
  • Ethnic Politics
  • European Union
  • Foreign Policy
  • Gender and Politics
  • Human Rights and Politics
  • Indian Politics
  • International Relations
  • International Organization (Politics)
  • International Political Economy
  • Irish Politics
  • Latin American Politics
  • Middle Eastern Politics
  • Political Behaviour
  • Political Economy
  • Political Institutions
  • Political Methodology
  • Political Communication
  • Political Philosophy
  • Political Sociology
  • Political Theory
  • Politics and Law
  • Politics of Development
  • Public Policy
  • Public Administration
  • Qualitative Political Methodology
  • Quantitative Political Methodology
  • Regional Political Studies
  • Russian Politics
  • Security Studies
  • State and Local Government
  • UK Politics
  • US Politics
  • Browse content in Regional and Area Studies
  • African Studies
  • Asian Studies
  • East Asian Studies
  • Japanese Studies
  • Latin American Studies
  • Middle Eastern Studies
  • Native American Studies
  • Scottish Studies
  • Browse content in Research and Information
  • Research Methods
  • Browse content in Social Work
  • Addictions and Substance Misuse
  • Adoption and Fostering
  • Care of the Elderly
  • Child and Adolescent Social Work
  • Couple and Family Social Work
  • Direct Practice and Clinical Social Work
  • Emergency Services
  • Human Behaviour and the Social Environment
  • International and Global Issues in Social Work
  • Mental and Behavioural Health
  • Social Justice and Human Rights
  • Social Policy and Advocacy
  • Social Work and Crime and Justice
  • Social Work Macro Practice
  • Social Work Practice Settings
  • Social Work Research and Evidence-based Practice
  • Welfare and Benefit Systems
  • Browse content in Sociology
  • Childhood Studies
  • Community Development
  • Comparative and Historical Sociology
  • Economic Sociology
  • Gender and Sexuality
  • Gerontology and Ageing
  • Health, Illness, and Medicine
  • Marriage and the Family
  • Migration Studies
  • Occupations, Professions, and Work
  • Organizations
  • Population and Demography
  • Race and Ethnicity
  • Social Theory
  • Social Movements and Social Change
  • Social Research and Statistics
  • Social Stratification, Inequality, and Mobility
  • Sociology of Religion
  • Sociology of Education
  • Sport and Leisure
  • Urban and Rural Studies
  • Browse content in Warfare and Defence
  • Defence Strategy, Planning, and Research
  • Land Forces and Warfare
  • Military Administration
  • Military Life and Institutions
  • Naval Forces and Warfare
  • Other Warfare and Defence Issues
  • Peace Studies and Conflict Resolution
  • Weapons and Equipment

Mental Representations: A dual coding approach

Mental Representations: A dual coding approach

Professor of Psychology

  • Cite Icon Cite
  • Permissions Icon Permissions

This work presents a systematic analysis of the psychological phenomena associated with the concept of mental representations — also referred to as cognitive or internal representations. A major restatement of a theory the author of this book first developed in his 1971 book ( Imagery and Verbal Processes ), this book covers phenomena from the earlier period that remain relevant today but emphasizes cognitive problems and paradigms that have since emerged more fully. It proposes that performance in memory and other cognitive tasks is mediated not only by linguistic processes but also by a distinct nonverbal imagery model of thought as well. It discusses the philosophy of science associated with the dual coding approach, emphasizing the advantages of empiricism in the study of cognitive phenomena and shows that the fundamentals of the theory have stood up well to empirical challenges over the years.

Personal account

  • Sign in with email/username & password
  • Get email alerts
  • Save searches
  • Purchase content
  • Activate your purchase/trial code
  • Add your ORCID iD

Institutional access

Sign in with a library card.

  • Sign in with username/password
  • Recommend to your librarian
  • Institutional account management
  • Get help with access

Access to content on Oxford Academic is often provided through institutional subscriptions and purchases. If you are a member of an institution with an active account, you may be able to access content in one of the following ways:

IP based access

Typically, access is provided across an institutional network to a range of IP addresses. This authentication occurs automatically, and it is not possible to sign out of an IP authenticated account.

Choose this option to get remote access when outside your institution. Shibboleth/Open Athens technology is used to provide single sign-on between your institution’s website and Oxford Academic.

  • Click Sign in through your institution.
  • Select your institution from the list provided, which will take you to your institution's website to sign in.
  • When on the institution site, please use the credentials provided by your institution. Do not use an Oxford Academic personal account.
  • Following successful sign in, you will be returned to Oxford Academic.

If your institution is not listed or you cannot sign in to your institution’s website, please contact your librarian or administrator.

Enter your library card number to sign in. If you cannot sign in, please contact your librarian.

Society Members

Society member access to a journal is achieved in one of the following ways:

Sign in through society site

Many societies offer single sign-on between the society website and Oxford Academic. If you see ‘Sign in through society site’ in the sign in pane within a journal:

  • Click Sign in through society site.
  • When on the society site, please use the credentials provided by that society. Do not use an Oxford Academic personal account.

If you do not have a society account or have forgotten your username or password, please contact your society.

Sign in using a personal account

Some societies use Oxford Academic personal accounts to provide access to their members. See below.

A personal account can be used to get email alerts, save searches, purchase content, and activate subscriptions.

Some societies use Oxford Academic personal accounts to provide access to their members.

Viewing your signed in accounts

Click the account icon in the top right to:

  • View your signed in personal account and access account management features.
  • View the institutional accounts that are providing access.

Signed in but can't access content

Oxford Academic is home to a wide variety of products. The institutional subscription may not cover the content that you are trying to access. If you believe you should have access to that content, please contact your librarian.

For librarians and administrators, your personal account also provides access to institutional account management. Here you will find options to view and activate subscriptions, manage institutional settings and access options, access usage statistics, and more.

Our books are available by subscription or purchase to libraries and institutions.

Month: Total Views:
October 2022 6
October 2022 1
October 2022 2
October 2022 5
October 2022 1
October 2022 1
October 2022 2
October 2022 2
October 2022 2
October 2022 3
October 2022 8
October 2022 3
October 2022 4
October 2022 30
October 2022 2
November 2022 2
November 2022 5
November 2022 1
November 2022 1
November 2022 6
November 2022 2
November 2022 2
November 2022 6
November 2022 2
November 2022 4
November 2022 2
November 2022 49
December 2022 7
December 2022 4
December 2022 8
December 2022 6
December 2022 6
December 2022 41
December 2022 1
December 2022 5
December 2022 6
December 2022 1
December 2022 13
December 2022 7
December 2022 9
December 2022 7
January 2023 3
January 2023 2
January 2023 1
January 2023 3
January 2023 2
January 2023 2
January 2023 4
January 2023 32
January 2023 1
January 2023 2
January 2023 2
January 2023 2
January 2023 12
January 2023 5
January 2023 8
January 2023 2
January 2023 1
January 2023 3
February 2023 4
February 2023 3
February 2023 1
February 2023 2
February 2023 4
February 2023 3
February 2023 1
February 2023 2
February 2023 45
February 2023 11
February 2023 5
February 2023 5
February 2023 5
February 2023 3
February 2023 1
February 2023 2
February 2023 3
February 2023 6
March 2023 7
March 2023 2
March 2023 3
March 2023 5
March 2023 7
March 2023 65
March 2023 6
March 2023 6
March 2023 4
March 2023 5
March 2023 7
March 2023 4
March 2023 4
March 2023 1
March 2023 8
March 2023 4
April 2023 2
April 2023 1
April 2023 1
April 2023 2
April 2023 4
April 2023 60
April 2023 1
April 2023 10
April 2023 9
April 2023 2
May 2023 7
May 2023 11
May 2023 1
May 2023 15
May 2023 7
May 2023 9
May 2023 4
May 2023 1
May 2023 8
May 2023 11
May 2023 41
May 2023 7
May 2023 5
May 2023 20
May 2023 9
May 2023 14
May 2023 1
May 2023 11
June 2023 4
June 2023 3
June 2023 1
June 2023 1
June 2023 3
June 2023 30
June 2023 1
June 2023 2
June 2023 2
June 2023 1
June 2023 1
July 2023 1
July 2023 4
July 2023 1
July 2023 3
July 2023 43
July 2023 7
July 2023 2
July 2023 1
July 2023 3
July 2023 4
July 2023 1
August 2023 3
August 2023 2
August 2023 3
August 2023 31
August 2023 2
August 2023 1
August 2023 3
August 2023 5
September 2023 4
September 2023 2
September 2023 3
September 2023 5
September 2023 4
September 2023 50
September 2023 2
September 2023 2
September 2023 3
September 2023 3
September 2023 3
September 2023 3
September 2023 15
September 2023 2
September 2023 1
October 2023 8
October 2023 9
October 2023 11
October 2023 14
October 2023 5
October 2023 2
October 2023 15
October 2023 9
October 2023 2
October 2023 9
October 2023 60
October 2023 15
October 2023 11
October 2023 7
October 2023 14
October 2023 16
October 2023 7
October 2023 3
November 2023 1
November 2023 3
November 2023 2
November 2023 4
November 2023 2
November 2023 2
November 2023 1
November 2023 3
November 2023 51
November 2023 6
November 2023 6
November 2023 7
November 2023 8
November 2023 4
December 2023 1
December 2023 2
December 2023 3
December 2023 2
December 2023 1
December 2023 45
December 2023 3
December 2023 1
December 2023 2
December 2023 1
December 2023 7
December 2023 1
December 2023 5
January 2024 8
January 2024 7
January 2024 6
January 2024 1
January 2024 5
January 2024 3
January 2024 7
January 2024 2
January 2024 5
January 2024 34
January 2024 6
January 2024 5
January 2024 3
January 2024 7
January 2024 9
January 2024 2
January 2024 11
January 2024 5
February 2024 5
February 2024 6
February 2024 6
February 2024 7
February 2024 4
February 2024 11
February 2024 1
February 2024 50
February 2024 2
February 2024 6
February 2024 4
February 2024 9
February 2024 17
February 2024 6
February 2024 3
March 2024 2
March 2024 2
March 2024 4
March 2024 1
March 2024 62
March 2024 1
March 2024 11
March 2024 9
March 2024 1
March 2024 6
April 2024 8
April 2024 4
April 2024 2
April 2024 3
April 2024 10
April 2024 6
April 2024 6
April 2024 12
April 2024 69
April 2024 8
April 2024 16
April 2024 9
April 2024 8
April 2024 5
May 2024 1
May 2024 3
May 2024 11
May 2024 68
May 2024 5
May 2024 1
May 2024 12
May 2024 3
May 2024 2
May 2024 6
June 2024 6
June 2024 5
June 2024 7
June 2024 9
June 2024 5
June 2024 53
June 2024 3
June 2024 5
June 2024 5
June 2024 1
June 2024 8
June 2024 14
June 2024 1
June 2024 5
June 2024 8
July 2024 1
July 2024 1
July 2024 1
July 2024 3
July 2024 12
  • About Oxford Academic
  • Publish journals with us
  • University press partners
  • What we publish
  • New features  
  • Open access
  • Rights and permissions
  • Accessibility
  • Advertising
  • Media enquiries
  • Oxford University Press
  • Oxford Languages
  • University of Oxford

Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the University's objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide

  • Copyright © 2024 Oxford University Press
  • Cookie settings
  • Cookie policy
  • Privacy policy
  • Legal notice

This Feature Is Available To Subscribers Only

Sign In or Create an Account

This PDF is available to Subscribers Only

For full access to this pdf, sign in to an existing account, or purchase an annual subscription.

  • Study Protocol
  • Open access
  • Published: 05 July 2024

Novel online enfacement illusion for investigating self-perception in mental disorders: an experimental study protocol

  • Jade Portingale 1 ,
  • David Butler 2 , 3 &
  • Isabel Krug 1  

Journal of Eating Disorders volume  12 , Article number:  94 ( 2024 ) Cite this article

Metrics details

Remote research methods and interventions for mental health disorders have become increasingly important, particularly for conditions like eating disorders (EDs). Embodiment illusions, which induce feelings of ownership over another person?s body or body parts, offer valuable insights into the mechanisms underlying self-perception issues in EDs and potential interventions. However, existing research using these illusions has been limited to face-to-face settings. We illustrate a novel online protocol to induce the enfacement illusion (embodiment illusion principles applied to one’s face) in an ED-based sample.

Participants complete a 2-hr virtual session with a researcher. First, baseline trait/state ED psychopathology measures and a self-face recognition task occur. Second, participants experience two testing blocks of the enfacement illusion involving synchronously and asynchronously mimicking a pre-recorded actor’s facial expressions. After each block, subjective and objective enfacement illusion measures occur alongside state ED psychopathology reassessment.

Successfully inducing enfacement illusions online could provide an affordable, accessible virtual approach to further elucidate the mechanistic role of self-perception disturbances across psychopathologies such as EDs. Moreover, this protocol may represent an innovative, remotely-delivered intervention strategy, as ‘enfacement’ over another face could update negative self-representations in a cost-effective, scalable manner.

Multisensory bodily (hereafter ‘embodiment’) illusions refer to the illusory experience of perceived ownership, agency, and self-location over another body or body part external to one’s own (e.g., a rubber hand or full virtual body) [ 1 , 2 ]. These illusions typically arise from synchronising visual input of an external body with tactile stimulation on one's own body and proprioceptive awareness of one’s actual body position and movements [ 3 ]. Embodiment illusions have been widely investigated in clinical populations with self-perception disturbances via both real and virtual reality (VR) settings [ 4 ], as they offer a means to enhance mechanistic understanding and potentially improve symptomatology. However, these illusions are yet to be conducted outside of a face-to-face environment: limiting more widespread research and potential interventions. Converging fields of research in recent decades have argued that self-perception issues (the inaccurate perception of oneself) are central to the development and maintenance of various mental disorders: for instance, alterations in body representation are linked to the onset and maintenance of eating disorders (EDs) [ 5 ], body dysmorphic disorder [ 6 ], schizophrenia [ 7 ], borderline personality disorder [ 8 ], and depression [ 9 ]. The current study protocol will present a novel online embodiment illusion paradigm applied to the face, with an example of its application in ED populations.

Limitations of current face-to-face research and intervention

The coronavirus disease 2019 (COVID-19) pandemic has made evident potential barriers to understanding and treating mental disorders outside of a face-to-face environment [ 10 ]. For instance, in a recent survey that investigated the impact of the current pandemic on ED researchers, respondents expressed high concerns about data collection and recruitment, with 20-40% of their current projects being stopped [ 10 ]. Moreover, a recent systematic scoping review [ 11 ] revealed that up to 61% of studies assessing individuals with various levels of eating pathology reported worsening ED symptoms during the COVID-19 pandemic. The rationale for online interventions for mental health is currently centred on enabling access for those unable to receive evidence-based treatments [ 12 , 13 ]. For instance, one Australian study reported an average delay of 5.3 years between ED symptom onset and treatment-seeking due to barriers such as costs, geographic constraints, wait times, and stigma [ 14 , 15 ]. Online interventions enable more flexible, cost-effective delivery reducing wait times over traditional face-to-face approaches [ 16 ], with support for their efficacy in treating conditions such as depression [ 17 ] and EDs [ 18 ].

‘Classic’ embodiment illusions involving tactile input

The perception of our body emerges from the combination of a continuous stream of information from the body to the brain [ 19 ]. This process entails the integration of various sensory signals (i.e., visual, tactile, proprioceptive, and/or interceptive), termed ‘multisensory integration’, which ultimately combine to form a unified and coherent body representation [ 19 ]. However, as the process of multisensory integration is continuous and relatively malleable, distortions of body perception can arise.

This is widely evidenced via embodiment illusions (e.g., the experimentally induced feeling of ownership over a fake/virtual body or body part) which show that it is possible to modulate our internal body representation by inducing multisensory conflicts (e.g., across vision and touch) [ 2 , 4 ]. These illusions typically involve tactile, visual, and proprioceptive input. In the classic rubber hand illusion (RHI; Fig. 1 ) [ 1 , 2 ], synchronous stroking between the rubber hand and the participant’s own (unseen) hand elicits illusory embodiment assessed subjectively via self-report (e.g., perceived ownership and/or agency over the external body/body part) [ 20 ] and objectively such as via changes in body size estimation [ 21 ]. Full-body [ 22 ] and enfacement illusions [ 23 ] employ similar multisensory integration principles (visual-tactile-proprioceptive input, hereafter referred to as ‘tactile’ stimulation) to induce ownership over an entire body or face, respectively, that is external to one’s own. Full-body illusions are often conducted in a VR setting and typically involve the same measures as the RHI. Enfacement illusions are typically induced using a computer screen in a laboratory setting and involve self-report questionnaires (e.g., ownership over the other’s face, appearance similarity) and objective measurement (e.g., self-other discrimination task) [ 24 ] (described below).

figure 1

Example depiction of the classic rubber hand illusion procedure with tactile stimulation (i.e., stroking). A participant’s hand is hidden from their view as they observe a rubber hand placed in their view. Both hands are synchronously stroked. Reproduced, with permission, from [ 82 ]

Individuals with various mental disorders such as EDs [ 25 ], schizophrenia [ 26 ], and borderline personality disorder [ 27 ] demonstrate increased susceptibility to these tactile illusions (e.g., a stronger sense of perceived ‘ownership’ over an external body or face typically following synchronous versus asynchronous stimulation), offering insight into the multisensory basis of self-perception issues. Moreover, these illusions can temporarily update distorted bodily representations to improve symptomatology such as reducing body size overestimation post-embodying healthy-weight avatars in individuals with anorexia nervosa [ 21 , 28 ]. This is grounded in the notion that these illusions–in manipulating the multisensory integration processes underlying self-perception—enable individuals with EDs to temporarily merge their negative self-image with that of another body depicting desirable physical attributes, improving current self-perception [ 21 , 28 ].

‘Tactile-reduced’ embodiment illusions

Recently, tactile-less embodiment via mere synchronous visual-proprioceptive input without tactile stimulation has been supported [ 29 ]. For instance, researchers have shown that mere observation of a motionless body part from a first-person perspective induced the RHI in hemiplegic patients [ 30 ] and the full-body illusion via VR in non-clinical individuals [ 31 ]. Curiously, when compared, embodiment was shown to be stronger following tactile-less relative to tactile stimulation [ 32 ], potentially due to the human tendency to weigh visual information over other somatosensory cues [ 30 , 33 ]. Another tactile-reduced embodiment approach employs visual-motor-proprioceptive synchrony by mimicking bodily movements, successfully inducing full-body illusions within VR [ 34 , 35 ]. Paralleling tactile approaches, tactile-reduced embodiment illusions show increased susceptibility in disorders such as EDs [ 31 ] and schizophrenia [ 36 ] and can improve symptoms such as fear of weight gain post-embodying healthy-weight avatars in anorexia nervosa [ 37 ].

Importance of enfacement illusion research

Recent decades have seen the continued emergence of improved, yet cost-affordable VR technologies, with numerous benefits (e.g., enhanced ecological validity by immersing individuals in real-world situations) [ 38 ]. Despite this, it is worth considering simpler and more cost-effective embodiment illusion paradigms that do not require excessive technology (e.g., VR headsets), yet maintain ecological validity (e.g., can be conducted in one’s home environment).

The tactile-reduced enfacement illusion, induced through mimicking the facial movements of an actor on a computer screen [ 24 ], holds the potential for studying self-perception without VR and external stimuli (e.g., a rubber hand). Furthermore, examining self-face perception via enfacement illusions is crucial for several reasons. The face commonly represents our most distinguishing physical feature [ 39 ] and aberrations in face processing such as facial emotion recognition and interpreting expressions are observed in various psychopathologies including alexithymia, autism spectrum disorder, schizophrenia, and mood disorders [ 40 , 41 , 42 ]. Moreover, distortions in self-face perception are linked to body dysmorphic disorder and EDs [ 43 , 44 ], where the face is pivotal in attractiveness judgments [ 45 ]. Exploring multisensory mechanisms underlying self-face representation may contribute to an advanced aetiological understanding and interventions for EDs and related conditions. Moreover, as self-face representation is intimately tied to self-awareness [ 46 ], this line of research will connect with the broader literature on self-awareness and psychopathology.

A few studies have explored susceptibility to the tactile and tactile-reduced enfacement illusion in relation to mental disorders within laboratory settings. For instance, individuals with borderline personality disorder [ 47 ] and schizophrenia [ 48 , 49 ] have been shown to experience greater susceptibility to tactile enfacement than healthy controls. Regarding intervention, one study demonstrated that experiencing tactile-reduced enfacement with a smiling face via VR (i.e., participants controlled the movements of a virtual face by moving and touching their own face) improved mood in a non-clinical sample as a result of mood migration [ 50 ]. This demonstrates the potential utility of tactile and tactile-reduced enfacement methods in understanding and improving mental disorder symptomatology. However, all enfacement illusion research to date has required face-to-face administration in controlled laboratory settings, preventing more widespread application.

The current study protocol

The present study protocol aims to investigate a novel procedure inducing the tactile-reduced enfacement illusion online via facial expression mimicry, illustrated through application in ED populations. As eating pathology varies from non-clinical and sub-threshold levels in the general community to clinically severe EDs [ 51 ], findings from treatment-seeking populations may not fully capture the spectrum of EDs. Hence, we will recruit a sample of women from the community and ED clinics/organisations, encompassing a continuum of ED risk ranging from no history to current, recovered or lifetime ED diagnosis to optimise analyses. The primary aim is to assess whether our online paradigm successfully induces the enfacement illusion by comparing subjective and objective measures of illusion strength across synchronous and asynchronous time points. If so, we will evaluate whether susceptibility to the enfacement illusion differs by ED risk level and whether experiencing the enfacement illusion impacts ED symptomatology and facial and body-related image disturbances. We hypothesise that: (i) our procedure will induce the enfacement illusion (i.e., objective and subjective measures of illusion strength will be stronger/greater post-synchronous relative to asynchronous timing); (ii) individuals with (versus without) ED risk will show increased susceptibility to the enfacement illusion; and, (iii) experiencing the enfacement illusion will improve ED symptomatology and facial and body image disturbances in general, but will be more pronounced in individuals with (versus without) ED risk.

Successfully inducing enfacement online may provide a more affordable, accessible virtual approach enhancing embodiment illusion-based self-perception research across psychopathologies, particularly when face-to-face procedures are unfeasible. Moreover, this protocol may facilitate innovative remotely-delivered interventions leveraging facial embodiment to update maladaptive self-representations. Establishing this paradigm holds important implications for continued self-perception research and intervention accessibility.

Study design

The proposed study is experimental. In a single, 2-hr online session, participants will undergo baseline assessment (T0) of trait/state questionnaires and an objective self-other perception task, followed by two randomised testing phases (T1, T2) involving enfacement illusion induction with subjective and objective enfacement illusion measures and state questionnaires post-illusion.

Participant recruitment and eligibility criteria

Participants will be recruited from a university and the general community (social media websites, snowballing methods, and personal contacts of the researchers), alongside ED clinics/private practices, ED organisation websites, and ED-related social media pages. Inclusion criteria: (i) women (cis-gender); (ii) aged≥18 years; (iii) Caucasian or Eastern/Southeastern Asian (for model congruency enhancing enfacement/embodiment illusion effects [ 53 , 54 , 55 ]); (iv) fluent in English; and (v) access to a smartphone and computer/laptop.

Eliciting the enfacement illusion involves mimicking the facial expressions of ethnicity-matched models in synchronous/asynchronous videos [ 26 , 50 ]. Stimuli were created across a pilot phase obtaining ratings of model images to select neutrally-valenced models, and will be generated in the experimental phase involving the creation of face-morphing videos.

Pilot phase

Face images of models.

Images of 10 Caucasian and 10 Eastern/Southeastern Asian female models’ faces (aged≥18 years) were obtained via snowballing. These ethnicities were chosen given that individuals from our target population are primarily Caucasian or Eastern/Southeastern Asian. All images were standardised by having models against a white wall under similar lighting conditions and facing front-on (eye-level) with a neutral expression. Using PhotoScape X (Version 4), as per Tsakiris [ 56 ], all images were grey-scaled and given a black background. We then applied an oval frame around the face to remove non-facial attributes (e.g. ears, hair, background). All images were then collated into an online questionnaire via the online survey platform Qualtrics. To minimise bias, an independent community sample of 60 women (30 Caucasian; 30 Eastern/Southeastern Asian) ethnicity-matched to models rated images for facial attractiveness, facial adiposity, likeability, and emotional expression as these factors are known/suggested to bias enfacement illusion effects [ 57 , 58 , 59 , 60 , 61 ]. For example, facial adiposity was assessed using a scale from 1 ( very underweight ) to 7 ( very overweight ). The final 10 models (6 Caucasian and 4 Eastern/Southeastern Asian) were average on all ratings Footnote 1 . We combined Eastern/Southeastern Asian faces into a broad ‘Asian’ category, as previous face recognition research has treated them as a single category [ 62 , 63 ], as do some face databases (e.g., Chicago Face Database) [ 64 ].

Stimulation video

Over a videoconferencing platform (Zoom), the 10 selected models recorded 150 s videos alternating between exaggerated smiles and a neutral expression every 10 s (see Fig. 2 ). This is consistent with prior protocols [ 50 , 65 ] and research demonstrating that enfacement is stronger for models with positively-valenced faces [ 57 , 59 ]. Videos were slightly longer than prior protocols which were typically 120 s [ 49 ] to increase the stimulation phase and likelihood of enfacement. Videos were standardised by having models against a white wall under similar lighting conditions and facing front-on (eye-level). Using iMovie, audible sound effects were inserted at the start of each facial expression—smile and then neutral expression—to pace the delivery of each facial expression. The final models received $20 (AUD) e-gift cards as compensation.

figure 2

Example depiction of female stimulation video using facial mimicy. Here, the model alternates between a neutral facial expression (left and right) and smiling facial expression (centre) in 10 s iterations for a duration of 150 s

Experimental phase

Face-morphing videos.

Participants’ selfie photographs (described below under procedure) will be standardised as per the pilot and flipped horizontally (i.e., mirror-reversed) to match their self-perception (e.g [ 49 ]). Using random allocation, each selfie will be morphed with a same-ethnicity (Caucasian or Asian) model’s facial photograph in proportional steps from 100% other to 100% self [ 56 , 66 ]. Videos will last 100 s, with 100 frames [ 56 ]. The other-self direction was chosen given prior research suggesting that only this direction elicits enfacement [ 20 ]. The morphed“other” face matches that in the stimulation video.

At T0: Eating Attitudes Test- 26 [EAT-26]) [ 67 ] assesses ED symptomatology. Using defined cut-off scores on the EAT-26, participants will be stratified into an at-risk ED group (scores ≥ 20) and a not-at-risk ED group (scores < 20).

At T0, and T1 and T2 post-illusion, state-based measures:

Body Satisfaction Scale (BSS) [ 68 ]; assesses body satisfaction / dissatisfaction with 16 body parts, including a validated 7 items for the body subscale and 7 items for the head/face subscale.

Shortened 10-item Body Image Concern Inventory (BICI-10 [ 69 ]; adapted from Littleton et al. [ 70 ]) assesses dysmorphic appearance concern.

Facial adiposity scale (adopted from Coetzee et al. [ 71 ]); assesses perceived facial adiposity (i.e., weight).

Facial attractiveness scale (adopted from Coetzee et al. [ 71 , 72 ]; assesses perceived facial attractiveness.

Self-other discrimination task [ 24 , 56 , 58 ]; participants watch a video of morphed images gradually transitioning from a face that was 100% model (0% self) to 100% self (0% model) and will be required to stop the video (by pressing the space bar with their left-index finger) when the image appears more like the self than the model. Enfacement is believed to occur if participants accept a larger percentage of the model’s facial features as their own (i.e., stop the video later) following synchronous relative to asynchronous interpersonal multisensory stimulation and/or baseline levels of self-other discrimination ability.

At T1, T2 post-illusion: State-based enfacement questionnaire [ 58 ]; adapted from Tajadura-Jiménez et al. [ 20 ], assessing subjective enfacement across self-identification, similarity, and affect.

Post-experiment: Self-reported demographic characteristics (age, gender, current height and weight, main language spoken at home, ethnicity, sexual orientation, highest education completed, and marital status) and ED diagnosis (lifetime, current, or recovered).

Experimental procedure

See Fig. 3 for a simplified graphic depiction of the experimental procedure. Before the 2 h virtual held over Zoom, participants receive requirements for computer/room set-up (i.e., seated comfortably, approximately 50 cm from the screen, in a quiet, well-lit room) and the selfie. Following consent, participants take the selfie and then complete T0 measures while the researcher prepares the face morphing video using their selfie. Next, participants complete a training protocol involving discriminating their face from an unfamiliar face (none of the assigned models) and completing two face morphing movies (involving well-known celebrities) to ensure comprehension of face identification/self-other discrimination tasks.

figure 3

Simplified graphic depiction of the experimental procedure for eating disorder populations containing the three main assessment blocks. EAT-26 = Eating Attitudes Test 26-item; BSS = Body Satisfaction Scale; BICI-10 = Body Image Concern Inventory 10-item short version; FAds = Facial Adiposity Scale; FAts = Facial Attractiveness Scale

The main experiment will have two counterbalanced blocks of synchronous/asynchronous tactile-reduced stimulation, each with three phases: (1) Two trials of a mimicry task involving watching the enfacement video and mimicking the model’s facial expressions (see Fig. 4 for a depiction). Participants perform the same facial expression as the model observed in the video (i.e., the participant will smile when the model smiles) and the opposite expression to the model observed in the same video (i.e., the participant smiles when the model displays a neutral expression) during synchronous and asynchronous timing conditions, respectively; (2) The self-other discrimination task and enfacement questionnaire; (3) State-based questionnaires. Post-experiment, participants complete demographic measures and are debriefed and compensated. Standardised procedures are enforced, including mandatory breaks (5 min between each block to prevent carry-over effects and 30 sec between trials of the stimulation video) and strict protocol adherence.

figure 4

Example depiction of the online enfacement illusion procedure showing the synchronous facial mimicry condition with a smiling expression (i.e., tactile-reduced stimulation)

Statistical analysis

Sample size calculation.

A target sample ≥ 128 participants (≥ 64 per ED risk group as defined via the EAT-26 [ 67 ]) was determined based on an a-priori power analysis conducted in G*Power [ 73 ] to guarantee a statistical power and statistical level of 95% to detect a medium effect size ( f = 0.25) [ 74 ] in a mixed between-within-subjects ANCOVA assessing ED risk group differences in enfacement susceptibility and improvements across time-points. Analyses will control for important demographic variables (e.g., age). These parameters are consistent with the only previous study assessing the embodiment illusion among a clinical ED population that reported a power analysis [ 28 ] Footnote 2 .

Missing data

Participants with missing data on the EAT-26 will be excluded, as their risk group categorisation is essential. For state-based body image measures, up to 5% missingness will be acceptable given the large target sample size. Minimal missingness on these measures may be imputed if data are missing completely at random or missing at random. Participants with significant missingness will be excluded if data are not missing at random, as imputation could introduce bias.

Planned analysis

All analyses will be run using IBM SPSS Statistics (Version 28). Pending that obtained data do not significantly violate ANCOVA assumptions, testing hypotheses will involve mixed between-within-subjects ANCOVAs for each dependent variable. Hypotheses 1–2 will involve a 2 (ED risk versus non-risk) x 3 (Timing; baseline vs. synchronous vs. asynchronous) ANCOVA for objective enfacement (self-other discrimination task); and a 2 (ED risk versus non-risk) x 2 (Timing; synchronous vs. asynchronous) ANCOVA for subjective enfacement (enfacement questionnaire). Covariates will include age, BMI, ethnicity, and alexithymia. Testing hypothesis 3 will involve a series of 2 (ED risk versus non-risk) x 3 (Timing; baseline vs. synchronous vs. asynchronous) ANCOVAs for each body and face-related image disturbance outcome: (i) body dissatisfaction (via the body-related subscale of the BSS); (ii) head/face dissatisfaction (via the head/face-related subscale of the BSS); (iii) dysmorphic concern (via the BICI-10); (iv) facial attractiveness and facial adiposity (via the facial attractiveness and adiposity questionnaires, respectively).

Ethical issues and dissemination plan

This study has been approved by the local ethics committee (University of Melbourne). Experimental stimuli (stimulation videos and model images) will be made available on Open Science Framework.

Within mental disorders, particularly EDs, bodily misperception remains a critical concern [ 4 ], yet research and interventions targeting its underlying mechanisms are limited. The facial region, representing a highly salient aspect of identity, has received even less attention when considering misperception. While technological advancements have increased online ED interventions such as ‘e-therapy’ [ 12 , 13 ], these methods have not targeted bodily-self-perception. The experimental induction of the enfacement illusion online represents a promising new tool for studying and intervening in facial (and broader bodily) misperception. However, these illusions have not been conducted online outside of face-to-face settings.

The present study will evaluate the effectiveness of a novel online procedure to induce the enfacement illusion via facial mimicry. If effective, this tactile-reduced embodiment illusion method may then shed light on the mechanisms underpinning, and potentially improve, ED symptoms. Its anticipated effectiveness is based on: (1) growing support for experimentally inducing the enfacement illusion within laboratory settings using tactile-reduced stimulation (i.e., facial mimicry) involving mere visual-motor-proprioceptive input [ 24 ], and (2) parallels between bodily and self-face perception, with consistent and growing evidence that embodiment illusions offer insights into bodily misperception in EDs and a means to improve ED symptoms (e.g [ 21 , 28 ]).

This study represents a crucial first step in exploring an innovative approach to comprehending and treating EDs. The proposed online technique could enhance our understanding of self-perception disturbances central to these disorders, whilst highlighting deficits in multisensory integration as a possible underlying factor. Moreover, its potential therapeutic value, when incorporated alongside established interventions like cognitive behavior therapy [ 75 ], may offer a promising multidimensional treatment avenue targeting the perceptual, cognitive-affective, and behavioral dimensions of body/face image disturbance. Since tactile-reduced embodiment (e.g [ 38 ]) and enfacement illusions (e.g [ 50 ]) offer insight into bodily-self-misperception across other mental disorders (e.g., body dysmorphic disorder, schizophrenia, borderline personality disorder, depression), the current method’s broad applicability warrants investigation.

Strengths, limitations, and future directions

Strengths of the proposed study include the implementation and assessment of a novel online procedure to induce the enfacement illusion, potentially shedding light on mechanisms underpinning bodily (self-face) misperception and improving ED (and other mental health) symptoms. It enables widespread access/availability of research and intervention.

Limitations include potential cognitive fatigue effects from the lengthy experimental procedure which may be particularly detrimental to ED populations [ 76 ] and the mixed community and clinical sample assessed based on ED risk potentially yielding smaller effects than a clinical ED sample compared to matched healthy controls. We encourage future researchers to adapt the protocol to clinical populations, ensuring verification of diagnoses. Moreover, future research is needed to determine the best protocol for inducing the enfacement illusion, such as comparing tactile vs. tactile-reduced procedures, examining ideal stimulation duration/number of trials, and investigating facial expressions. For instance, existing research in this area involving face-to-face studies has produced mixed results regarding the latter; e.g., Maister et al. [ 77 ] demonstrated that fearful facial expressions yielded a stronger enfacement illusion than other conditions (happiness, disgust, neutral), whilst Beck et al. [ 78 ] found no effect of negative facial expressions (fear, anger) relative to a neutral expression on the enfacement illusion. Future researchers should assess differential effects of factors such as stimulation duration/emotional expression and examine the procedure’s applicability across mental disorders and demographics (e.g., gender, ethnicity). Accordingly, recommendations for adjusting the procedure may be made. Furthermore, experiences of plastic surgery and teeth straightening, common in body-image-disturbed populations [ 79 , 80 ], could potentially influence the results. We encourage future iterations of the current protocol to screen for such experiences in demographic questions to account for their potential influence in the analyses. Lastly, recognising calls in the broader psychological literature for more fine-grained analyses separating major Asian ethnic groups [ 81 ], future researchers should attempt to precisely account for ethnic categories. For example, East Asian participants could rate the extent to which their model (East Asian or Southeast Asian) was perceived as ‘typical’ of their ethnic category using a visual analogue scale. This would confirm that participants perceive their assigned model as a member of their ethnic in-group, avoiding potential negative evaluations and enfacement effects due to perceived out-group status [ 52 ]. Irrespective of limitations, our research represents a promising first step in this emerging field.

Data availability

No datasets were generated or analysed during the current study.

Four of the models were only rated as average in terms of attractiveness and not rated on the other measures as they were adopted from a previous study.

Please note that their analysis was based on a simpler ANOVA, thus, producing a smaller target sample of 58 participants, 29 per ED and HC group. Moreover, given the paucity of literature, it is unclear whether the effect size could be large.

Abbreviations

  • Eating disorder

Rubber hand illusion

Virtual reality

Longo MR, Schüür F, Kammers MP, Tsakiris M, Haggard P. What is embodiment? A psychometric approach. Cognition. 2008;107(3):978–98. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2007.12.004 .

Tsakiris M. My body in the brain: a neurocognitive model of body-ownership. Neuropsychologia. 2010;48(3):703–12. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.neuropsychologia.2009.09.034 .

Article   PubMed   Google Scholar  

Botvinick M, Cohen J. Rubber hands ‘feel’touch that eyes see. Nature. 1998;391(6669):756. https://doi.org/10.1038/35784 .

Matamala-Gomez M, Maselli A, Malighetti C, Realdon O, Mantovani F, Riva G. Virtual body ownership illusions for mental health: a narrative review. J Clin Med. 2021;10(1):139. https://doi.org/10.3390/jcm10010139 .

Article   PubMed   PubMed Central   Google Scholar  

Glashouwer KA, van der Veer RM, Adipatria F, de Jong PJ, Vocks S. The role of body image disturbance in the onset, maintenance, and relapse of anorexia nervosa: a systematic review. Clin Psychol Rev. 2019;74:101771. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cpr.2019.101771 .

Mitchison D, Mond J. Epidemiology of eating disorders, eating disordered behaviour, and body image disturbance in males: a narrative review. J Eat Disorders. 2015;3(1):1–9. https://doi.org/10.1186/s40337-015-0058-y .

Article   Google Scholar  

Pienkos E, Giersch A, Hansen M, Humpston C, McCarthy-Jones S, Mishara A, Nelson B, Park S, Raballo A, Sharma R, Thomas N. Hallucinations beyond voices: a conceptual review of the phenomenology of altered perception in psychosis. Schizophr Bull. 2019;45(Supplement1):S67–77. https://doi.org/10.1093/schbul/sby057 .

Merrett Z, Rossell SL, Castle DJ. Comparing the experience of voices in borderline personality disorder with the experience of voices in a psychotic disorder: a systematic review. Australian New Z J Psychiatry. 2016;50(7):640–8. https://doi.org/10.1177/0004867416632595 .

Harshaw C. Interoceptive dysfunction: toward an integrated framework for understanding somatic and affective disturbance in depression. Psychol Bull. 2015;141(2):311. https://doi.org/10.1037%2Fa0038101.

Weissman RS, Bauer S, Thomas JJ. Access to evidence-based care for eating disorders during the COVID‐19 crisis. Int J Eat Disord. 2020;53(5):639–46. https://doi.org/10.1002/eat.23279 .

Linardon J, Shatte A, Tepper H, Fuller-Tyszkiewicz M. A survey study of attitudes toward, and preferences for, e‐therapy interventions for eating disorder psychopathology. Int J Eat Disord. 2020;53(6):907–16. https://doi.org/10.1002/eat.23268 .

Kazdin AE, Fitzsimmons-Craft EE, Wilfley DE. Addressing critical gaps in the treatment of eating disorders. Int J Eat Disord. 2017;50(3):170–89. https://doi.org/10.1002/eat.22670 .

Weissman RS, Rosselli F. Reducing the burden of suffering from eating disorders: unmet treatment needs, cost of illness, and the quest for cost-effectiveness. Behav Res Ther. 2017;88:49–64. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.brat.2016.09.006 .

Hamilton A, Mitchison D, Basten C, Byrne S, Goldstein M, Hay P, Heruc G, Thornton C, Touyz S. Understanding treatment delay: perceived barriers preventing treatment-seeking for eating disorders. Australian New Z J Psychiatry. 2022;56(3):248–59. https://doi.org/10.1177/00048674211020102 .

Ali K, Farrer L, Fassnacht DB, Gulliver A, Bauer S, Griffiths KM. Perceived barriers and facilitators towards help-seeking for eating disorders: a systematic review. Int J Eat Disord. 2017;50(1):9–21. https://doi.org/10.1002/eat.22598 .

Andersson G, Titov N, Dear BF, Rozental A, Carlbring P. Internet-delivered psychological treatments: from innovation to implementation. World Psychiatry. 2019;18(1):20–8. https://doi.org/10.1002/wps.20610 .

Ebert DD, Zarski AC, Christensen H, Stikkelbroek Y, Cuijpers P, Berking M, Riper H. Internet and computer-based cognitive behavioral therapy for anxiety and depression in youth: a meta-analysis of randomized controlled outcome trials. PLoS ONE. 2015;10(3):e0119895. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0119895 .

Waller G, Pugh M, Mulkens S, Moore E, Mountford VA, Carter J, Wicksteed A, Maharaj A, Wade TD, Wisniewski L, Farrell NR. Cognitive-behavioral therapy in the time of coronavirus: clinician tips for working with eating disorders via telehealth when face‐to‐face meetings are not possible. Int J Eat Disord. 2020;53(7):1132–41. https://doi.org/10.1002/eat.23289 .

Riva G. The neuroscience of body memory: From the self through the space to the others. Cortex. 2018;104:241-60 https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cortex.2017.07.013 .

Tajadura-Jiménez A, Grehl S, Tsakiris M. The other in me: interpersonal multisensory stimulation changes the mental representation of the self. PLoS ONE. 2012;7(7):e40682. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0040682 .

Keizer A, Smeets MA, Postma A, van Elburg A, Dijkerman HC. Does the experience of ownership over a rubber hand change body size perception in anorexia nervosa patients? Neuropsychologia. 2014;62:26–37. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.neuropsychologia.2014.07.003 .

Maselli A, Slater M. The building blocks of the full body ownership illusion. Front Hum Neurosci. 2013;7:83.

Porciello G, Bufalari I, Minio-Paluello I, Di Pace E, Aglioti SM. The ‘Enfacement’illusion: a window on the plasticity of the self. Cortex. 2018;104:261–75. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cortex.2018.01.007 .

Estudillo AJ, Bindemann M. Can gaze-contingent mirror-feedback from unfamiliar faces alter self-recognition? Q J Experimental Psychol. 2017;70(5):944–58. https://doi.org/10.1080/17470218.2016.1166253 .

Eshkevari E, Rieger E, Longo MR, Haggard P, Treasure J. Persistent body image disturbance following recovery from eating disorders. Int J Eat Disord. 2014;47(4):400–9. https://doi.org/10.1002/eat.22219 .

Thakkar KN, Nichols HS, McIntosh LG, Park S. Disturbances in body ownership in schizophrenia: evidence from the rubber hand illusion and case study of a spontaneous out-of-body experience. PLoS ONE. 2011;6(10):e27089. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0027089 .

Neustadter ES, Fineberg SK, Leavitt J, Carr MM, Corlett PR. Induced illusory body ownership in borderline personality disorder. Neurosci Conscious. 2019;2019(1):niz017. https://doi.org/10.1093/nc/niz017 .

Keizer A, van Elburg A, Helms R, Dijkerman HC. A virtual reality full body illusion improves body image disturbance in anorexia nervosa. PLoS ONE. 2016;11(10):e0163921. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0163921 .

An Z, Krug I, Portingale J, Butler D. Mirror, mirror, on the wall: during pandemics, how can self-perception research in people with eating disorders happen at all? J Eat Disorders. 2022;10(1):89. https://doi.org/10.1186/s40337-022-00608-8 .

Martinaud O, Besharati S, Jenkinson P, Fotopoulou A. Ownership illusions in patients with body delusions: different neural profiles of visual capture and disownership. Cortex. 2017;87:174–85. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.Cortex.2016.09.025 .

Carey M, Preston C. Investigating the components of body image disturbance within eating disorders. Front Psychiatry. 2019;10:635. https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyt.2019.00635 .

Carey M, Crucianelli L, Preston C, Fotopoulou A. The effect of visual capture towards subjective embodiment within the full body illusion. Sci Rep. 2019;9(1):2889. https://doi.org/10.1038/s41598-019-39168-4 .

van Stralen HE, van Zandvoort MJ, Kappelle LJ, Dijkerman HC. The Rubber Hand Illusion in a patient with hand disownership. Perception. 2013;42(9):991–3. https://doi.org/10.1068/p7583 .

Ferrer-Garcia M, Porras-Garcia B, González-Ibañez C, Gracia-Blanes M, Vilalta-Abella F, Pla-Sanjuanelo J, Riva G, Dakanalis A, Achotegui-Loizate J, Talarn-Caparrós A, Ribas-Sabate J. Does owning a fatter virtual body increase body anxiety in college students? Annual Review of CyberTherapy and Telemedicine; 2017.

Neyret S, Bellido Rivas AI, Navarro X, Slater M. Which body would you like to have? The impact of embodied perspective on body perception and body evaluation in immersive virtual reality. Front Rob AI. 2020;7:31. https://doi.org/10.3389/frobt.2020.00031 .

Rossetti I, Romano D, Florio V, Doria S, Nisticò V, Conca A, Mencacci C, Maravita A. Defective embodiment of alien hand uncovers altered sensorimotor integration in schizophrenia. Schizophr Bull. 2020;46(2):294–302. https://doi.org/10.1093/schbul/sbz050 .

Malighetti C, Chirico A, Serino S, Cavedoni S, Matamala-Gomez M, Stramba-Badiale C, Mancuso V, Corno G, Polli N, Cacciatore C, Persani L. Manipulating body size distortions and negative body-related memories in patients with Anorexia Nervosa: a virtual reality-based pilot study. Annual Review of CyberTherapy and Telemedicine; 2020.

Bell IH, Nicholas J, Alvarez-Jimenez M, Thompson A, Valmaggia L. Virtual reality as a clinical tool in mental health research and practice. Dialogues in clinical neuroscience. 2022 Apr 1. https://doi.org/10.31887/DCNS.2020.22.2/lvalmaggia .

Sheehan MJ, Nachman MW. Morphological and population genomic evidence that human faces have evolved to signal individual identity. Nature communications. 2014 Sep 16;5(1):4800. https://doi.org/10.1038/ncomms5800 .

Westwood H, Kerr-Gaffney J, Stahl D, Tchanturia K. Alexithymia in eating disorders: systematic review and meta-analyses of studies using the Toronto Alexithymia Scale. J Psychosom Res. 2017;99:66–81. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jpsychores.2017.06.007 .

Bortolon C, Capdevielle D, Salesse RN, Raffard S. Self-face recognition in schizophrenia: an eye-tracking study. Front Hum Neurosci. 2016;10:3. https://doi.org/10.3389/fnhum.2016.00003 .

Quevedo K, Harms M, Sauder M, Scott H, Mohamed S, Thomas KM, Schallmo MP, Smyda G. The neurobiology of self face recognition among depressed adolescents. J Affect Disord. 2018;229:22–31. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jad.2017.12.023 .

Buhlmann U, Etcoff NL, Wilhelm S. Facial attractiveness ratings and perfectionism in body dysmorphic disorder and obsessive-compulsive disorder. J Anxiety Disord. 2008;22(3):540–7. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.janxdis.2007.05.004 .

Hrabosky JI, Cash TF, Veale D, Neziroglu F, Soll EA, Garner DM, Strachan-Kinser M, Bakke B, Clauss LJ, Phillips KA. Multidimensional body image comparisons among patients with eating disorders, body dysmorphic disorder, and clinical controls: a multisite study. Body Image. 2009;6(3):155–63. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.bodyim.2009.03.001 .

Rieger E, Prasetya K, Christensen BK, Shou Y. Identifying the contingencies of self-worth associated with eating disorder symptoms: the use of choice based conjoint analysis. Int J Eat Disord. 2021;54(12):2167–79. https://doi.org/10.1002/eat.23634 .

Suddendorf T, Butler DL. The nature of visual self-recognition. Trends Cogn Sci. 2013;17(3):121–7. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.tics.2013.01.004 .

De Meulemeester C, Lowyck B, Panagiotopoulou E, Fotopoulou A, Verhaest Y, Luyten P. More Malleable Self?Other Boundaries in Borderline Personality Disorder: A Study using the Enfacement Illusion. Self-other distinction in borderline personality disorder. 2021:95. https://doi.org/10.1037/per0000415 .

Ferroni F, Ardizzi M, Sestito M, Lucarini V, Daniel BD, Paraboschi F, Tonna M, Marchesi C, Gallese V. Shared multisensory experience affects others–boundary: the enfacement illusion in schizophrenia. Schizophr Res. 2019;206:225–35. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.schres.2018.11.018 .

Sandsten KE, Nordgaard J, Kjaer TW, Gallese V, Ardizzi M, Ferroni F, Petersen J, Parnas J. Altered self-recognition in patients with schizophrenia. Schizophr Res. 2020;218:116–23. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.schres.2020.01.022 .

Ma K, Sellaro R, Lippelt DP, Hommel B. Mood migration: how enfacing a smile makes you happier. Cognition. 2016;151:52–62. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2016.02.018 .

Hart LM, Granillo MT, Jorm AF, Paxton SJ. Unmet need for treatment in the eating disorders: a systematic review of eating disorder specific treatment seeking among community cases. Clin Psychol Rev. 2011;31(5):727–35. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cpr.2011.03.004 .

Murnen SK, Smolak L. Gender and eating disorders. The Wiley handbook of eating disorders. 2015 Apr 30:352–66.

Ehrsson HH. Multisensory processes in body ownership. Multisensory perception. 2020 Jan 1:179–200 https://doi.org/10.1016/B978-0-12-812492-5.00008-5 .

Riemer M, Trojan J, Beauchamp M, Fuchs X. The rubber hand universe: on the impact of methodological differences in the rubber hand illusion. Neurosci Biobehavioral Reviews. 2019;104:268–80. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.neubiorev.2019.07.008 .

Tsakiris M. The multisensory basis of the self: from body to identity to others. Q J Experimental Psychol. 2017;70(4):597–609. https://doi.org/10.1080/17470218.2016.1181768 .

Tsakiris M. Looking for myself: current multisensory input alters self-face recognition. PLoS ONE. 2008;3(12):e4040. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0004040 .

Epley N, Whitchurch E. Mirror, mirror on the wall: enhancement in self-recognition. Pers Soc Psychol Bull. 2008;34(9):1159–70. https://doi.org/10.1177/0146167208318601 .

Panagiotopoulou E, Filippetti ML, Tsakiris M, Fotopoulou A. Affective touch enhances self-face recognition during multisensory integration. Sci Rep. 2017;7(1):12883. https://doi.org/10.1038/s41598-017-13345-9 .

Verosky SC, Todorov A. Generalization of affective learning about faces to perceptually similar faces. Psychol Sci. 2010;21(6):779–85. https://doi.org/10.1177/0956797610371965 .

Bufalari I, Lenggenhager B, Porciello G, Serra Holmes B, Aglioti SM. Enfacing others but only if they are nice to you. Front Behav Neurosci. 2014;8:102. https://doi.org/10.3389/fnbeh.2014.00102 .

Re DE, Perrett DI. The effects of facial adiposity on attractiveness and perceived leadership ability. Q J Experimental Psychol. 2014;67(4):676–86. https://doi.org/10.1080/17470218.2013.825635 .

Lee JK, Gregson C, Janssen SM, Estudillo AJ. Cultural modulation effects on the self-face advantage: do caucasians find their own faces faster than Chinese? Q J Experimental Psychol. 2023;76(8):1724–39. https://doi.org/10.1177/17470218221142158 .

Leong BQ, Estudillo AJ, Hussain Ismail AM. Holistic and featural processing’s link to face recognition varies by individual and task. Sci Rep. 2023;13(1):16869. https://doi.org/10.1038/s41598-023-44164-w .

Ma DS, Correll J, Wittenbrink B. The Chicago face database: a free stimulus set of faces and norming data. Behav Res Methods. 2015;47:1122–35. https://doi.org/10.3758/s13428-014-0532-5 .

Sforza A, Bufalari I, Haggard P, Aglioti SM. My face in yours: Visuo-tactile facial stimulation influences sense of identity. Soc Neurosci. 2010;5(2):148–62. https://doi.org/10.1080/17470910903205503 .

Abrosoft Fantamorph. Abrosoft Fantamorph Professional 5.0: 2020. http://www.fantamorph.com/index.html .

Garner DM, Olmsted MP, Bohr Y, Garfinkel PE. The eating attitudes test: psychometric features and clinical correlates. Psychol Med. 1982;12(4):871–8. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0033291700049163 .

Slade PD, Dewey ME, Newton T, Brodie D, Kiemle G. Development and preliminary validation of the body satisfaction scale (BSS). Psychol Health. 1990;4(3):213–20. https://doi.org/10.1080/08870449008400391 .

Collison J, Mahlberg J. Psychometric evaluation of the body image concern inventory in an undergraduate sample. Clin Psychol. 2019;23(2):112–23. https://doi.org/10.1111/cp.12169 .

Littleton HL, Axsom D, Pury CL. Development of the body image concern inventory. Behav Res Ther. 2005;43(2):229–41. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.brat.2003.12.006 .

Coetzee V, Perrett DI, Stephen ID. Facial adiposity: a cue to health? Perception. 2009;38(11):1700–11. https://doi.org/10.1068/p6423 .

Penton-Voak IS, Jones BC, Little AC, Baker S, Tiddeman B, Burt DM, Perrett DI. Symmetry, sexual dimorphism in facial proportions and male facial attractiveness. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London. Series B: Biological Sciences. 2001;268(1476):1617-23. https://doi.org/10.1098/rspb.2001.1703 .

Faul F, Erdfelder E, Lang AG, Buchner A. G* power 3: a flexible statistical power analysis program for the social, behavioral, and biomedical sciences. Behav Res Methods. 2007;39(2):175–91. https://doi.org/10.3758/BF03193146 .

Cohen J. Statistical power analysis for the behavioral sciences. Volume 3. Academic; 2013 Sep. https://doi.org/10.4324/9780203771587 .

Fairburn CG. Cognitive behavior therapy and eating disorders. Guilford Press; 2008 Apr. p. 21.

Ralph-Nearman C, Williams BM, Ortiz AM, Smith AR, Levinson CA. Pinpointing core and pathway symptoms among sleep disturbance, anxiety, worry, and eating disorder symptoms in anorexia nervosa and atypical anorexia nervosa. J Affect Disord. 2021;294:24–32. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jad.2021.06.061 .

Maister L, Banissy MJ, Tsakiris M. Mirror-touch synaesthesia changes representations of self-identity. Neuropsychologia. 2013;51(5):802–8. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.neuropsychologia.2013.01.020 .

Beck B, Cardini F, L davas E, Bertini C. The enfacement illusion is not affected by negative facial expressions. PLoS ONE. 2015;10(8):e0136273. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0136273 .

Coughlin JW, Schreyer CC, Sarwer DB, Heinberg LJ, Redgrave GW, Guarda AS. Cosmetic surgery in inpatients with eating disorders: attitudes and experience. Body Image. 2012;9(1):180–3. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.bodyim.2011.10.007 .

Vashi NA. Obsession with perfection: body dysmorphia. Clin Dermatol. 2016;34(6):788–91. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.clindermatol.2016.04.006 .

Gelfand MJ, Denison EE. Moving beyond the West vs. the rest: understanding variation within Asian groups and its societal consequences. Proc Natl Acad Sci. 2020;117(10):5100–2. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.2000930117 .

Mussap AJ, Salton N. A ‘rubber-hand’illusion reveals a relationship between perceptual body image and unhealthy body change. J Health Psychol. 2006;11(4):627–3. https://doi.org/10.1177/1359105306065022 .

Download references

Acknowledgements

Not applicable.

The University of Melbourne funded this project.

Author information

Authors and affiliations.

School of Psychological Sciences, The University of Melbourne, Melbourne, VIC, 3051, Australia

Jade Portingale & Isabel Krug

Faculty of Psychology and Counselling, The Cairnmillar Institute, Melbourne, VIC, Australia

David Butler

Department of Psychology, Counselling and Therapy, LaTrobe University, Melbourne, VIC, Australia

You can also search for this author in PubMed   Google Scholar

Contributions

All authors contributed to the conceptualisation and methodology of the manuscript. J.P. wrote the main manuscript text, prepared figures, and edited the main text after review. I.K. and D.B. assisted with reviewing and editing the manuscript and were responsible for supervision and project administration. All authors reviewed the final manuscript.

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jade Portingale .

Ethics declarations

Ethical approval and consent to participate.

This study has been approved by the local ethics committee (The University of Melbourne) in accordance with Australia’s National Statement on Ethical Conduct in Human Research (2007).

Reference Number: 2022-21318-28803-8.

Project Title: Mirror, Mirror on the Wall, That is not what I look like at all: Exploring Self-Perception.

Informed consent to participate will be obtained from all subjects and/or their legal guardian(s).

Consent for publication

All authors have provided consent for publication. Informed consent has been obtained from all subjects and/or their legal guardian(s) for publication of identifying information/images in an online open-access publication.

Competing interests

The authors declare no competing interests.

Additional information

Publisher’s note.

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Open Access This article is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License, which permits use, sharing, adaptation, distribution and reproduction in any medium or format, as long as you give appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the source, provide a link to the Creative Commons licence, and indicate if changes were made. The images or other third party material in this article are included in the article’s Creative Commons licence, unless indicated otherwise in a credit line to the material. If material is not included in the article’s Creative Commons licence and your intended use is not permitted by statutory regulation or exceeds the permitted use, you will need to obtain permission directly from the copyright holder. To view a copy of this licence, visit http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/ . The Creative Commons Public Domain Dedication waiver ( http://creativecommons.org/publicdomain/zero/1.0/ ) applies to the data made available in this article, unless otherwise stated in a credit line to the data.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article.

Portingale, J., Butler, D. & Krug, I. Novel online enfacement illusion for investigating self-perception in mental disorders: an experimental study protocol. J Eat Disord 12 , 94 (2024). https://doi.org/10.1186/s40337-024-01026-8

Download citation

Received : 18 March 2024

Accepted : 17 May 2024

Published : 05 July 2024

DOI : https://doi.org/10.1186/s40337-024-01026-8

Share this article

Anyone you share the following link with will be able to read this content:

Sorry, a shareable link is not currently available for this article.

Provided by the Springer Nature SharedIt content-sharing initiative

  • Self-perception
  • Facial perception
  • Enfacement illusion
  • Embodiment illusion
  • Mental health
  • Tactile-reduced

Journal of Eating Disorders

ISSN: 2050-2974

mental representation

SEP home page

  • Table of Contents
  • Random Entry
  • Chronological
  • Editorial Information
  • About the SEP
  • Editorial Board
  • How to Cite the SEP
  • Special Characters
  • Advanced Tools
  • Support the SEP
  • PDFs for SEP Friends
  • Make a Donation
  • SEPIA for Libraries
  • Entry Contents

Bibliography

Academic tools.

  • Friends PDF Preview
  • Author and Citation Info
  • Back to Top

Concepts are the building blocks of thoughts. Consequently, they are crucial to such psychological processes as categorization, inference, memory, learning, and decision-making. This much is relatively uncontroversial. But the nature of concepts—the kind of things concepts are—and the constraints that govern a theory of concepts have been the subject of much debate (Margolis & Laurence 1999, Margolis & Laurence 2015). This is due, at least in part, to the fact that disputes about concepts often reflect deeply opposing approaches to the study of the mind, to language, and even to philosophy itself. In this entry, we provide an overview of theories of concepts, and outline some of the disputes that have shaped debates surrounding the nature of concepts. The entry is organized around five significant issues that are focal points for many theories of concepts. Not every theory of concepts takes a stand on each of the five, but viewed collectively these issues show why the theory of concepts has been such a rich and lively topic in recent years. The five issues are: (1) the ontology of concepts, (2) the structure of concepts, (3) empiricism and nativism about concepts, (4) concepts and natural language, and (5) concepts and conceptual analysis.

  • 1.1 Concepts as mental representations

1.2 Concepts as abilities

1.3 concepts as abstract objects, 1.4 is the issue merely terminological, 2.1 the classical theory, 2.2 the prototype theory, 2.3 the theory theory, 2.4 conceptual atomism, 2.5 pluralism and eliminativism, 3.1 renewed interest in the empiricism/nativism dispute, 3.2 empiricism about concepts, 3.3 nativism about concepts, 4.1 can there be concepts without language, 4.2 the priority between language and concepts, 4.3 linguistic determinism and linguistic relativity, 5.1 attractions of conceptual analysis, 5.2 objections to conceptual analysis, other internet resources, related entries, 1. the ontology of concepts.

We begin with the issue of the ontological status of a concept. The three main options are to identify concepts with mental representations, with abilities, and with abstract objects such as Fregean senses.

1.1. Concepts as mental representations

The first of these views maintains that concepts are psychological entities, taking as its starting point the representational theory of the mind (RTM). According to RTM, thinking occurs in an internal system of representation. Beliefs and desires and other propositional attitudes enter into mental processes as internal symbols. For example, Sue might believe that Dave is taller than Cathy, and also believe that Cathy is taller than Ben, and together these may cause Sue to believe that Dave is taller than Ben. Her beliefs would be constituted by mental representations that are about Dave, Cathy and Ben and their relative heights. What makes these beliefs, as opposed to desires or other psychological states, is that the symbols have the characteristic causal-functional role of beliefs. (RTM is usually presented as taking beliefs and other propositional attitudes to be relations between an agent and a mental representation (e.g., Fodor 1987). But given that the relation in question is a matter of having a representation with a particular type of functional role, it is simpler to say that occurrent beliefs just are mental representations with this functional role.)

Many advocates of RTM take the mental representations involved in beliefs and other propositional attitudes to have internal structure. Accordingly, the representations that figure in Sue’s beliefs would be composed of more basic representations. For theorists who adopt the mental representation view of concepts, concepts are identified with these more basic representations.

Early advocates of RTM (e.g., Locke (1690/1975) and Hume (1739/1978)) called these more basic representations ideas , and often took them to be mental images. But modern versions of RTM assume that much thought is not grounded in mental images. The classic contemporary treatment maintains, instead, that the internal system of representation has a language-like syntax and a compositional semantics. According to this view, much of thought is grounded in word-like mental representations . This view is often referred to as the language of thought hypothesis (Fodor 1975). However, the analogy with language isn’t perfect; obviously, the internal symbol system must lack many of the properties associated with a natural language. Nonetheless, like a natural language, the internal system’s formulae are taken to have subject/predicate form and to include logical devices, such as quantifiers and variables. In addition, the content of a complex symbol is supposed to be a function of its syntactic structure and the contents of its constituents. Returning to Sue’s beliefs, the supposition is that they are composed of such symbols as DAVE, CATHY and TALLER and that her beliefs represent what they do in virtue of the contents of these symbols and how they are arranged .

The mental representation view of concepts is the default position in cognitive science (Carey 2009, Pinker 2007) and enjoys widespread support in the philosophy of mind, particularly among philosophers who view their work as being aligned with research in cognitive science (e.g., Carruthers 2006, Millikan 2000, Fodor 2003, Margolis & Laurence 2007). [ 1 ] Supporters of this view argue for it on explanatory grounds. They maintain that concepts and structured mental representations play a crucial role in accounting for the productivity of thought (i.e., the fact that human beings can entertain an unbounded number of thoughts), in explaining how mental processes can be both rational and implemented in the brain, and in accommodating the need for structure-sensitive mental processes (Fodor 1987; see also the entry language of thought hypothesis ).

Critics of this view argue that it is possible to have propositional attitudes without having explicitly entertained the relevant mental representations. Daniel Dennett (1977), for example, argues that most people believe zebras don’t wear overcoats in the wild —and a million other similar facts—even though they have never stopped to consider such matters. Dennett also notes that computing systems can lack representations corresponding to the explanations we cite in characterizing and predicting their behavior. For example, it may make perfect sense to say of a chess-playing computer that it thinks that it is good to get one’s queen out early, even though we know from how the computer is programmed that it has no representation with that very content (see Dennett 1978, 1987 for these and related criticisms and Fodor 1987 and Manfredi 1993 for responses).

Other critics claim that RTM is too closely associated with commonsense psychology, which they argue should be abandoned as a stagnant and degenerate research program (Churchland 1981; see entry eliminative materialism ), or that developments in computational modeling (esp. connectionism and dynamic systems theory) offer alternatives, particularly to the language of thought version of RTM (e.g., see Clark 1993, Van Gelder 1995, Elman et al. 1996, McClelland et al. 2010; see Fodor & Pylyshyn 1988, Marcus 2001, and Gallistel & King 2009 for critical discussion of theories that don’t employ combinatorial structure.)

According to the abilities view, it’s wrong to maintain that concepts are mental particulars—concepts are neither mental images nor word-like entities in a language of thought. Rather, concepts are abilities that are peculiar to cognitive agents (e.g., Dummett 1993, Bennett & Hacker 2008, Kenny 2010). The concept CAT, for example, might amount to the ability to discriminate cats from non-cats and to draw certain inferences about cats.

While the abilities view is maintained by a diverse group of philosophers, the most prominent reason for adopting the view is a deep skepticism about the existence and utility of mental representations, skepticism that traces back Ludwig Wittgenstein (1953/1958). One of the most influential arguments along these lines claims that mental representations are explanatorily idle because they reintroduce the very sorts of problems they are supposed to explain. For example, Michael Dummett cautions against trying to explain knowledge of a first language on the model of knowledge of a second language. In the case of a second language, it is reasonable to suppose that understanding the language involves translating its words and sentences into words and sentences of one’s first language. But according to Dummett, one can’t go on to translate words and sentences of one’s first language into a prior mental language. “[T]here is really no sense to speaking of a concept’s coming into someone’s mind. All we can think of is some image coming to mind which we take as in some way representing the concept, and this gets us no further forward, since we still have to ask in what his associating that concept with that image consists” (Dummett 1993, p. 98). In other words, the mental representation itself is just another item whose significance bears explaining. Either we are involved in a vicious regress, having to invoke yet another layer of representation (and so on indefinitely) or we might as well stop with the external language and explain its significance directly. (For critical discussion of this type of regress argument, see Fodor 1975, Crane 2015, Laurence & Margolis 1997).

Not surprisingly, critics of the abilities view argue in the other direction. They note difficulties that the abilities view inherits by its rejection of mental representations. One is that the view is ill-equipped to explain the productivity of thought; another is that it can say little about mental processes. And if proponents of the abilities view remain neutral about the existence of mental representations, they open themselves to the criticism that explication of these abilities is best given in terms of underlying mental representations and processes (see Fodor 1968 and Chomsky 1980 for general discussion of the anti-intellectualist tradition in the philosophy of mind).

An alternative conception of concepts takes concepts to be abstract objects of one type or another. The idea behind this view is that concepts are the meanings (or “contents”) of words and phrases as opposed to mental objects or mental states. This type of view has most prominently been associated with the view that concepts are Fregean senses (e.g., Peacocke 1992, Zalta 2001), so it is this version of the view that concepts are abstract objects that we will focus on here. For proponents of this view, concepts, as meanings, mediate between thought and language, on the one hand, and referents, on the other. An expression without a referent (“Pegasus”) needn’t lack a meaning, since it still has a sense. Similarly, the same referent can be associated with different expressions (e.g., “Eric Blair” and “George Orwell”) because they convey different senses. Senses are more discriminating than referents. Each sense has a unique perspective on its referent—a mode of presentation which represents the referent in a particular way. Differences in cognitive content trace back to differences in modes of presentation. It’s for this reason that the thought that George Orwell is Eric Blair lacks the triviality of the thought that George Orwell is George Orwell even though George Orwell and Eric Blair are the same person. Philosophers who take concepts to be senses particularly emphasize this feature of senses. Christopher Peacocke, for example, locates the subject matter of a theory of concepts as follows: “Concepts C and D are distinct if and only if there are two complete propositional contents that differ at most in that one contains C substituted in one or more places for D , and one of which is potentially informative while the other is not” (Peacocke 1992, p. 2). In other words, C and D embody differing modes of presentation. (See the entry Frege for discussion of the sense/reference distinction and for more on the explanatory functions associated with senses. To avoid terminological confusion, we should note that Frege himself did not use the term "concept" for senses, but rather for the referents of predicates. Similarly, it is worth noting that Frege uses the term "thought" to stand for propositions, so for Frege thoughts are not psychological states at all but rather the meanings of psychological states.)

The view that concepts are Fregean senses, like the abilities view, is generally held by philosophers who are opposed to identifying concepts with mental representations. Peacocke himself doesn’t go so far as to argue that mental representations are explanatorily idle, but he does think that mental representations are too fine-grained for philosophical purposes. “It is possible for one and the same concept to receive different mental representations in different individuals” (Peacocke 1992, p. 3). He is also concerned that identifying concepts with mental representations rules out the possibility of there being concepts that human beings have never entertained, or couldn’t ever entertain.

If we accept that a thinker’s possession of a concept must be realized by some subpersonal state involving a mental representation, why not say simply that the concept is the mental representation? Just this proposal is made by Margolis and Laurence (1999, 77). Mental representations that are concepts could even be typed by the corresponding possession condition of the sort I favour. This seems to me an entirely legitimate notion of a kind of mental representation; but it is not quite the notion of a concept. It can, for instance, be true that there are concepts human beings may never acquire, because of their intellectual limitations, or because the sun will expand to eradicate human life before humans reach a stage at which they can acquire these concepts. ‘There are concepts that will never be acquired’ cannot mean or imply ‘There are mental representations which are not mental representations in anyone’s mind’. If concepts are individuated by their possession conditions, on the other hand, there is no problem about the existence of concepts that will never be acquired. They are simply concepts whose possession conditions will never be satisfied by any thinkers. (Peacocke, 2005, p. 169).

Advocates of the mental representation view would respond to these arguments by invoking the type/token distinction with respect to mental representations. Just as two speakers can each produce distinct instances (that is, tokens)of the same type of word (e.g., the word “chair”), different thinkers’ minds can produce distinct instances (that is, tokens) of the same type of mental representation (e.g., the mental representation CHAIR). How does this help with the present objection? According to the mental representation view, to say that there are concepts that haven’t been acquired by anyone is just to say that, for some types of mental representations, there has not yet been a token in anyone’s mind; to say that some concepts will never be acquired by anyone is just to say that, for some types of mental representations, there never will be a token in anyone’s mind (Margolis & Laurence 2007).

Critics of the sense-based view have questioned the utility of appealing to such abstract objects (Quine 1960). One difficulty stems from the fact that senses, as abstract entities, stand outside of the causal realm. The question then is how we can access these objects. Advocates of the Fregean sense view describe our access to senses by means of the metaphor of “grasping”—we are said to grasp the sense of an expression. But grasping here is just a metaphor for a cognitive relation that needs to be explicated. Moreover, though senses are hypothesized as providing different modes of presentation for referents, it is not clear why senses themselves do not generate the mode of presentation problem (Fodor 1998). Since they are external to our minds, just as referents typically are, it isn’t clear why we can’t stand in different epistemic relations towards them just as we can to referents. In the same way that we can have different modes of presentation for a number (the only even prime, the sum of one and one, Tim’s favorite number, etc.), we ought to be able to have different modes of presentation for a given sense.

Stepping back from the details of these three views, there is no reason, in principle, why the different views of concepts couldn’t be combined in various ways. For instance, one might maintain that concepts are mental representations that are typed in terms of the Fregean senses they express (see Margolis & Laurence 2007 for discussion).

One might also question whether the dispute about ontology is a substantive dispute. Perhaps there is only a terminological issue about which things ought to be granted the label “concepts”. If so, why not just call mental representations “concepts 1 ”, the relevant abilities “concepts 2 ”, senses “concepts 3 ”, and leave it at that?

However, the participants in the dispute don’t generally view it as a terminological one. Perhaps this is because they associate their own theories of concepts with large-scale commitments about the way that philosophers should approach the study of mind and language. Undoubtedly, from Dummett’s perspective, philosophers who embrace the mental representation view also embrace RTM, and RTM, as he sees it, is fundamentally misguided. Likewise, from Fodor’s perspective, RTM is critical to the study of the mind, so an approach like Dummett’s, which disallows RTM, places inappropriate a priori constraints on the study of the mind. Given that the disagreement about concepts is so closely tied to such clearly substantive explanatory disagreements, the debate about what concepts are would itself seem to be a substantive disagreement about what sorts of entities are best suited to playing the central explanatory roles associated with concepts.

Of course, it is possible to introduce new theoretical terms (“concepts 1 ”, “concepts 2 ”, and “concepts 3 ”) for the different theoretical posits made by the different approaches we have been considering (the ability view, the mental representation view, and the abstract object view), and then reconstruct the debate regarding these different approaches as a merely terminological disagreement about which of these terms we should use. But notice that it is possible to do the same thing even for clear-cut substantive debates. For example, we could introduce new terms for moral goodness as understood by deontologists (“good 1 ”) and as understood by consequentialists (“good 2 ”), and then reconstruct the debate about what moral goodness consists in as a merely terminological disagreement about which term we should use, “good 1 ” or “good 2 ”. Or we could introduce “human 1 ” for humans as understood by standard evolutionary accounts (according to which humans have nonhuman primate ancestors) and “human 2 ” for humans understood by creationists (according to which they don't), and reconstruct the debate between these different approaches as a merely terminological issue about which term we should use, “human 1 ” or “human 2 ”. The danger, of course, is that this would drain the very idea of a merely terminological debate of its utility and obscure very real differences between different sorts of disagreements (e.g., stipulative vs. substantive) that would all end up counting as “merely terminological”.

In the remainder of this entry we will frame questions from the perspective of the mental representation view, but readers who prefer a different view can reframe the issues in their preferred terms. For example, the questions “Can there be concepts without language?” is typically understood on the mental representation view as asking whether a pre-linguistic or non-linguistic agent can entertain mental representations of a particular kind. If one adopts the view that concepts are abstract objects, the corresponding question might be whether a pre-linguistic or non-linguistic agent can stand in the concept possession relation to concepts understood as abstract objects of a certain type. And if one adopts the view that concepts are abilities, the corresponding question might be whether a pre-linguistic or non-linguistic agent can have the abilities that are constitutive of concept possession.

2. The structure of concepts

Just as thoughts are composed of concepts, many concepts are themselves complex entities that are composed of other concepts or more basic representational components. In this section, we look at different proposals about the structure of what are often called lexical concepts . Roughly speaking, these are concepts that tend to be associated with individual words in natural language—concepts like BIRD and WALK as opposed to manifestly complex concepts like NOCTURNAL ANIMALS THAT LIVE IN TREES or TO WALK AIMLESSLY ON A NEWLY PAVED ROAD. With BIRD and WALK and similar concepts, it isn’t obvious what type of internal structure (if any) they have, and this has led to a great deal of controversy (Margolis & Laurence 1999, Murphy 2002). Accounts of the structure of lexical concepts have focused on concepts for categories of objects, actions, and events rather than concepts for individuals. Our discussion will share this focus (see, e.g., Blok et al. 2005 and Levine 2010 for discussion of concepts of individuals).

In one way or another, all theories regarding the structure of concepts are developments of, or reactions to, the classical theory of concepts . According to the classical theory, a lexical concept C has definitional structure in that it is composed of simpler concepts that express necessary and sufficient conditions for falling under C. The stock example is the concept BACHELOR, which is traditionally said to have the constituents UNMARRIED and MAN. If the example is taken at face value, the idea is that something falls under BACHELOR if it is an unmarried man and only if it is an unmarried man. According to the classical theory, lexical concepts generally will exhibit this same sort of definitional structure. This includes such philosophically interesting concepts as TRUTH, GOODNESS, FREEDOM, and JUSTICE.

Before turning to other theories of conceptual structure, it’s worth pausing to see what’s so appealing about classical or definitional structure. Much of its appeal comes from the way it offers unified treatments of concept acquisition, categorization, and reference determination. In each case, the crucial work is being done by the very same components. Concept acquisition can be understood as a process in which new complex concepts are created by assembling their definitional constituents. Categorization can be understood as a psychological process in which a complex concept is matched to a target item by checking to see if each and every one of its definitional constituents applies to the target. And reference determination, we’ve already seen, is a matter of whether the definitional constituents do apply to the target.

These considerations alone would be enough to show why the classical theory has been held in such high regard. But the classical theory receives further motivation through its connection with a philosophical method that goes back to antiquity and that continues to exert its influence over contemporary thought. This is the method of conceptual analysis . Paradigmatic conceptual analyses offer definitions of concepts that are to be tested against potential counterexamples that are identified via thought experiments. Conceptual analysis is supposed to be a distinctively a priori activity that many take to be the essence of philosophy. To the extent that paradigmatic conceptual analyses are available and successful, this will convey support for the classical theory. Conversely, if the definitions aren’t there to be discovered, this would seem to put in jeopardy a venerable view of what philosophy is and how philosophical investigations ought to proceed (see section 5 below).

The classical theory has come under considerable pressure in the last forty years or so, not just in philosophy but in psychology and other fields as well. For psychologists, the main problem has been that the classical theory has difficulty explaining a robust set of empirical findings. At the center of this work is the discovery that certain categories are taken to be more representative or typical and that typicality scores correlate with a wide variety of psychological data (for reviews, see Smith & Medin 1981, Murphy 2002). For instance, apples are judged to be more typical than plums with respect to the category of fruit, and correspondingly apples are judged to have more features in common with fruit. There are many other findings of this kind. One other is that more typical items are categorized more efficiently. For example, subjects are quicker to judge that apples are a kind of fruit than to judge that plums are. The problem isn’t that the classical theory is inconsistent with results like these but that it does nothing to explain them.

In philosophy, the classical theory has been subjected to a number of criticisms but perhaps the most fundamental is that attempts to specify definitions for concepts have a poor track record. Quite simply, there are too few examples of successful definitional analyses, and certainly none that are uncontroversial (Wittgenstein 1953/1958, Fodor 1981). The huge literature on the analysis of knowledge is representative of the state of things. Since Edmund Gettier (1963) first challenged the traditional definition of KNOWLEDGE (as JUSTIFIED TRUE BELIEF), there has been widespread agreement among philosophers that the traditional definition is incorrect or at least incomplete (see the entry the analysis of knowledge )). But no one can seem to agree on what the correct definition is. Despite the enormous amount of effort that has gone into the matter, and the dozens of papers written on the issue, we are still lacking a satisfactory and complete definition. It could be that the problem is that definitions are hard to come by. But another possibility—one that many philosophers are now taking seriously—is that our concepts lack definitional structure.

What other type of structure could they have? A non-classical alternative that emerged in the second half of the twentieth century is the prototype theory (e.g., Hampton 2006). According to this theory, a lexical concept C doesn’t have definitional structure but has probabilistic structure in that something falls under C just in case it satisfies a sufficient number of properties encoded by C ’s constituents. The prototype theory has its philosophical roots in Wittgenstein’s (1953/1958) famous remark that the things covered by a term often share a family resemblance, and it has its psychological roots in Eleanor Rosch’s groundbreaking experimental treatment of much the same idea (Rosch & Mervis 1975, Rosch 1978). The prototype theory is especially at home in dealing with the typicality effects that were left unexplained by the classical theory. One standard strategy is to maintain that, on the prototype theory, categorization is to be understood as a similarity comparison process, where similarity is computed as a function of the number of constituents that two concepts hold in common. On this model, the reason apples are judged to be more typical than plums is that the concept APPLE shares more of its constituents with FRUIT. Likewise, this is why apples are judged to be a kind of fruit faster than plums are.

The prototype theory does well in accounting for a variety of psychological phenomena and it helps to explain why definitions may be so hard to produce. But the prototype theory has its own problems and limitations. One is that its treatment of categorization works best for quick and unreflective judgments. Yet when it comes to more reflective judgments, people go beyond the outcome of a similarity comparison. If asked whether a dog that is surgically altered to look like a raccoon is a dog or a raccoon, the answer for most of us, and even for children, is that it is remains a dog (see Keil 1989, Gelman 2003 for discussion). Another criticism that has been raised against taking concepts to have prototype structure concerns compositionality. When a patently complex concept has a prototype structure, it often has emergent properties, ones that don’t derive from the prototypes of its constituents (e.g., PET FISH encodes properties such as brightly colored, which have no basis in the prototype structure for either PET or FISH). Further, many patently complex concepts don’t even have a prototype structure (e.g., CHAIRS THAT WERE PURCHASED ON A WEDNESDAY) (Fodor & Lepore 1996, Fodor 1998; for responses to the arguments from compositionality, see Prinz 2002, Robbins 2002, Hampton & Jönsson 2012, and Del Pinal 2016).

One general solution that addresses all of these problems is to hold that a prototype constitutes just part of the structure of a concept. In addition, concepts have conceptual cores , which specify the information relevant to more considered judgments and which underwrite compositional processes. Of course, this just raises the question of what sort of structure conceptual cores have. One suggestion is that conceptual cores have classical structure (Osherson & Smith 1981, Landau 1982). This won’t do, however, since it just raises once again most of the problems associated with the classical theory (Laurence & Margolis 1999).

Another and currently more popular suggestion is that cores are best understood in terms of the theory theory of concepts . This is the view that concepts stand in relation to one another in the same way as the terms of a scientific theory and that categorization is a process that strongly resembles scientific theorizing (see, e.g., Carey 1985, 2009, Gopnik & Meltzoff 1997, Keil 1989). It’s generally assumed, as well, that the terms of a scientific theory are interdefined so that a theoretical term’s content is determined by its unique role in the theory in which it occurs.

The theory theory is especially well-suited to explaining the sorts of reflective categorization judgments that proved to be difficult for the prototype theory. For example, theory theorists maintain that children override perceptual similarity in assessing the situation where the dog is made to look like a raccoon, claiming that even children are in possession of a rudimentary biological theory. This theory tells them that being a dog isn’t just a matter of looking like a dog. More important is having the appropriate hidden properties of dogs—the dog essence (see Atran & Medin 2008 on folkbiology). Another advantage of the theory theory is that it is supposed to help to explain important aspects of conceptual development. Conceptual change in childhood is said to follow the same pattern as theory change in science.

One problem that has been raised against the theory theory is that it has difficulty in allowing for different people to possess the same concepts (or even for the same person to have the same concept over time). The reason is that the theory theory is holistic . A concept’s content is determined by its role in a theory, not by its being composed of just a handful of constituents. Since beliefs that enter people’s mental theories are likely to be different from one another (and are likely to change), there may be no principled basis for comparison (Fodor & Lepore 1992). Another problem with the theory theory concerns the analogy to theory change in science. The analogy suggests that children undergo radical conceptual reorganization in the course of cognitive development, but many of the central case studies have proved to be controversial on empirical grounds, with evidence that the relevant concepts are implicated in core knowledge systems that are enriched in development but not fundamentally altered (see Spelke & Kinzler 2007 on core knowledge). However, there are certain specific examples where radical conceptual reorganization is plausible, for instance, when children eventually develop a theory of matter that allows them to differentiate weight from density, and air from nothing (Carey 2009).

A radical alternative to all of the theories we’ve mentioned so far is conceptual atomism , the view that lexical concepts have no semantic structure (Fodor 1998, Millikan 2000). According to conceptual atomism, the content of a concept isn’t determined by its relation to other concepts but by its relation to the world.

Conceptual atomism follows in the anti-descriptivist tradition that traces back to Saul Kripke, Hilary Putnam, and others working in the philosophy of language (see Kripke 1972/80, Putnam 1975, Devitt 1981). Kripke, for example, argues that proper names function like mere tags in that they have no descriptive content (Kripke 1972/80). On a description theory one might suppose that “Gödel” means something like the discoverer of the incompleteness of arithmetic . But Kripke points out we could discover that Schmitt really discovered the incompleteness of arithmetic and that Gödel could have killed Schmitt and passed the work off as his own. The point is that if the description theory were correct, we would be referring to Schmitt when we say “Gödel”. But intuitively that’s not the case at all. In the imagined scenario, the sentence “Gödel discovered the incompleteness of arithmetic” is saying something false about Gödel, not something trivially true about the discoverer of the incompleteness of arithmetic, whoever that might be (though see Machery et al. 2004 on whether this intuition is universal and Genone 2012 for discussion of the role of intuitions in theories of reference). Kripke’s alternative account of names is that they achieve their reference by standing in a causal relation to their referents. Conceptual atomism employs a similar strategy while extending the model to all sorts of concepts, not just ones for proper names.

At present, the nature of conceptual structure remains unsettled. Perhaps part of the problem is that more attention needs to be given to the question of what explanatory work conceptual structure is supposed to do and the possibility that there are different types of structure associated with different explanatory functions. We’ve seen that conceptual structure is invoked to explain, among other things, typicality effects, reflective categorization, cognitive development, reference determination, and compositionality. But there is no reason to assume that a single type of structure can explain all of these things. As a result, there is no reason why philosophers shouldn’t maintain that concepts have different types of structure. For example, notice that atomism is largely motivated by anti-descriptivism. In effect, the atomist maintains that considerable psychological variability is consistent with concepts entering into the same mind-world causal relations, and that it’s the latter that determines a concept’s reference. But just because the mechanisms of reference determination permit considerable psychological variability doesn’t mean that there aren’t, in fact, significant patterns for psychologists to uncover. On the contrary, the evidence for typicality effects is impressive by any measure. For this reason, it isn’t unreasonable to claim that concepts do have prototype structure even if that structure has nothing to do with the determination of a concept’s referent. Similar considerations suggest that concepts may have theory-structure and perhaps other types of structure as well (see Laurence & Margolis 1999 on different types of conceptual structure).

One way of responding to the plurality of conceptual structures is to suppose that concepts have multiple types of structure. This is the central idea behind conceptual pluralism . According to one version of conceptual pluralism, suggested by Laurence & Margolis (1999), a given concept will have a variety of different types of structure associated with it as components of the concept in question. For example, concepts may have atomic cores that are linked to prototypes, internalized theories, and so on. On this approach, the different types of structure that are components of a given concept play different explanatory roles. Reference determination and compositionality have more to do with the atomic cores themselves and how they are causally related to things outside of the mind, while rapid categorization and certain inferences depend on prototype structure, and more considered inferences and reasoning depend upon theory structure. Many variants on this general proposal are possible, but the basic idea is that, while concepts have a plurality of different types of structure with different explanatory roles, this differing structure remains unified through the links to an atomic representation that provides a concept’s reference. One challenge for this type of account is to delineate which of the cognitive resources that are associated with a concept should be counted as part of its structure and which should not. As a general framework, the account is neutral regarding this question, but as the framework is filled in, clarification will be needed regarding the status of potential types of structure.

A different form of pluralism about conceptual structure doesn’t employ atomic cores but simply says that the prototype, theory, etc. are all themselves concepts (Weiskopf 2009). Rather than holding that a single concept (e.g., the concept CAT) has multiple types of structure as components, as in the first form of pluralism, this form takes each type of structure to be a concept on its own, resulting in a plurality of concepts (CAT 1 , CAT 2 , CAT 3 , etc). On this view, it is wrong to suppose that there is such a thing as the concept CAT. Instead, there are many cat-concepts, each with a different type of structure, where each is involved in just a subset of the high-level psychological processes associated with cats. CAT 1 , for example, might explain some instances of categorization and some inferences, while CAT 2 , CAT 3 , etc. explain others. What’s more, on this form of pluralism, people might also differ with respect to which kinds of cat-concepts they possess. And even if two people have a cat-concept with the same general type of structure (e.g., prototype structure), the concepts might still be rather different (treating prototypical cats as having rather different sorts of properties). In response to this second form of pluralism, some philosophers have argued that CAT 1 , CAT 2 , etc. may be better understood as different senses of a single CAT concept, on analogy with the different senses of a polysemous linguistic expression (e.g. the physical object sense and the content sense of “book”)(Vicente & Manrique 2016). Regardless of whether one accepts this point about polysemy, an important challenge facing this second (“multiple concepts”) version of pluralism is to explain why all of the different cat-concepts count as cat-concepts—that is, to explain what unifies the plurality of cat-concepts. A natural answer to this challenge is that what unifies them is that they all refer to the same category, the category of cats. But it is not so clear that they can all refer to the same category given the differences between the different cat-concepts and the way that they function in cognition. For example, a standard prototype structure would capture prototypical cats and exclude the highly unusual, atypical cats that a theory structure would cover, and consequently the two concepts would refer to distinct (though related) categories.

In all of its forms, pluralism about conceptual structure recognizes that concepts have diverse functions and that a corresponding variety of types of representations are needed to fulfill these functions. These same considerations have led some theorists to advocate concept eliminativism —the view that there are no concepts (Machery 2009). The reasoning behind concept eliminativism is that concept should be understood to be a natural kind if concepts exist at all, and that natural kinds ought to have significant commonalities that can be discovered using empirical methods, including commonalities that go well beyond the criteria that are initially used to characterize them. But according to concept eliminativists, there are no such commonalities that hold among the types of representations that pluralists embrace. Perhaps we need prototypes and theories and other types of representations for distinct higher-level cognitive processes, but they are too diverse to warrant the claim that they constitute a single kind. On this view, then, we should simply abandon the theoretical construct of a concept and refer only to more fine-grained types of representations, such as prototypes and theories. Opponents of concept eliminativism have responded to the eliminativist’s challenge in a number of ways. Some have argued that Machery’s criteria for elimination are simply too strong and that concept , understood as a higher-level kind or perhaps a functional kind, has great utility in psychological models of cognitive processes (e.g., Hampton 2010, Lalumera 2010, Strohminger & Moore 2010). Others have argued that Machery’s criteria for something’s being a natural kind are too restrictive and that his view would have the consequence of ruling out clear cases of legitimate higher-level kinds in science generally (e.g., Gonnerman & Weinberg 2010, Margolis & Laurence 2010). And others have argued that even if we grant Machery’s stringent criteria for being a natural kind, elimination wouldn’t follow, as concepts are natural kinds according to his criteria (Samuels & Ferreira 2010, Weiskopf 2010). (For further critical discussion of eliminativism, see the peer commentary that appears with Machery 2010 and the author’s response.)

3. Empiricism and nativism about concepts

One of the oldest questions about concepts concerns whether there are any innate concepts and, if so, how much of the conceptual system is innate. Empiricists maintain that there are few if any innate concepts and that most cognitive capacities are acquired on the basis of a few relatively simple general-purpose cognitive mechanisms. Nativists, on the other hand, maintain that there may be many innate concepts and that the mind has a great deal of innate differentiation into complex domain-specific subsystems.

In recent years, the debate over innate concepts has been reinvigorated as advances in cognitive science have provided philosophers with new tools for revisiting and refining the traditional dispute (see, e.g., Elman et al. 1996, Carruthers, Laurence, & Stich 2005, 2006, 2007, Johnson 2010). Philosophers have greatly benefited from empirical studies in such diverse fields as developmental psychology, evolutionary psychology, cognitive anthropology, neuroscience, linguistics, and ethology. Part of the philosophical interest of this work is that, while the scientists themselves take sides on the empiricist-nativist dispute, their theories and data are often open to interpretation.

As an example, one of the earliest lines of investigation that appeared to support traditional nativist conceptions of the mind was the study of language (Pinker 1994). Noam Chomsky and his followers argued that language acquisition succeeds even though children are only exposed to severely limited evidence about the structure of their language (Chomsky 1967, 1975, 1988; see also Laurence & Margolis 2001). Given the way that the final state (e.g., knowledge of English) outstrips the data that are available to children, we can only postulate that the human mind brings to language acquisition a complex set of language-specific dispositions. For Chomsky, these dispositions are grounded in a set of innate principles that constrain all possible human natural languages, viz., universal grammar (see Baker 2001 and Roberts 2017 on universal grammar).

Not surprisingly, many philosophers have questioned Chomsky’s position. The ensuing debate has helped to sharpen the crucial arguments and the extent to which nativist models should continue to command their central place in linguistic theory. (On the empiricist side, see Cowie 1999, Prinz 2002, and Sampson 2005; on the nativist side, see Laurence & Margolis 2001 and Pietroski & Crain 2012; see also the entry innateness and language and the entry philosophy of linguistics ). For instance, one of Fiona Cowie’s criticisms of Chomsky’s poverty of the stimulus argument is that any induction establishes a conclusion that outstrips the available data; hence, going beyond the data in the case of language acquisition doesn’t argue for innate language-specific dispositions—or else there would have to be a specific innate disposition for every induction we make (for an earlier version of this argument, see Putnam 1967, Goodman 1969). Both Laurence & Margolis (2001) and Crain & Pietroski (2001) respond by teasing out the various ways in which the problem of language acquisition goes beyond general problems about induction.

Traditionally, empiricists have argued that all concepts derive from sensations. Concepts were understood to be formed from copies of sensory representations and assembled in accordance with a set of general-purpose learning rules, e.g., Hume’s principles of association (Hume 1739/1978). On this view, the content of any concept must be analyzable in terms of its perceptual basis. Any purported concept that fails this test embodies a confusion. Thus David Hume ends his Enquiry with the famous remark:

When we run over libraries, persuaded of these principles, what havoc must we make? If we take in our hand any volume; of divinity or school metaphysics, for instance; let us ask, Does it contain any abstract reasoning concerning quantity or number? No. Does it contain any experimental reasoning concerning matter of fact and existence? No. Commit it then to the flames: For it can contain nothing but sophistry and illusion. (1748/1975, p. 165)

A similar doctrine was maintained by the logical positivists in the early Twentieth Century, though the positivists couched the view in linguistic terms (Ayer 1959). Their principle of verification required for a sentence or statement to be meaningful that it have empirical consequences, and, on some formulations of the principle, that the meaning of a sentence is the empirical procedure for confirming it (see the entry Vienna Circle ). Sentences that have no empirical consequences were deemed to be meaningless. Since a good deal of philosophy purports to express propositions that transcend all possible experience, the positivists were happy to say that these philosophical doctrines are entirely devoid of content and are composed of sentences that aren’t merely false but are literally gibberish.

Despite the unpopularity of verificationism (though see Dummett 1993, Wright 1989, and Dennett 1991), a growing number of philosophers are attracted to modified forms of empiricism, forms that primarily emphasize psychological relations between the conceptual system and perceptual and motor states, not semantic relations. An example is Lawrence Shapiro’s defense of the claim that the type of body that an organism has profoundly affects its cognitive operations as well as the way that the organism is likely to conceptualize the world (Shapiro 2004). Shapiro’s claim is directed against philosophical theories that willfully ignore contingent facts about human bodies as if a human mind could inhere in wildly different body types. Drawing on a number of empirical research programs, Shapiro cites examples that appear to support what he calls the embodied mind thesis , viz., that “minds profoundly reflect the bodies in which they are contained” (Shapiro 2004, p. 167).

Jesse Prinz (2002) also defends a modified form of empiricism. Prinz claims that “all (human) concepts are copies or combinations of copies of perceptual representations” (Prinz 2002, p. 108). Though the reference to copies is a nod to Hume, Prinz certainly doesn’t buy into Hume’s verificationism. In fact, Prinz adopts a causal theory of content of the kind that is usually associated with atomistic theories of concepts (e.g., Fodor 1998); thus Prinz’s theory of intentional content doesn’t require a concept to inherit the specifically perceptual content of its constituents. Nonetheless, Prinz thinks that every concept derives from perceptual representations. Perhaps the best way to understand the claim is that the mental representations that are activated when someone thinks about something—no matter what the thought—are representations that originate in neural circuits with perceptual or motor functions and that the mental process is affected by that origin. Suppose, for example, that one is thinking about a hammer. Then she is either activating representations that inhere in visual circuits, or representations involved in circuits that control hand shape, etc., and her thought is affected in some way by the primary function of these circuits. Following Lawrence Barsalou (1999; see also Barsalou et al. 2003), Prinz characterizes concept possession as a kind of simulation “tantamount to entering a perceptual state of the kind one would be in if one were to experience the thing it represents” (Prinz 2002, p. 150).

One challenge to this view of cognition is its implication for abstract concepts. It’s one thing to say that the concept HAMMER involves the activation of circuits related to hand shape; it’s quite another to identify representations tied to a particular sensory modality underlying such concepts as TRUTH, DEMOCRACY, ENTROPY, and NINETEEN (Adams & Campbell 1999, Brewer 1999). Logical concepts are also a challenge. Prinz suggests as a perceptual basis for the concept of disjunction that it is based on feelings of hesitation. However, his more considered view seems to be that logical concepts are best understood as operations, not representations. The resulting theory is one in which thoughts lack logical form. The trouble is that this makes it difficult to see how to distinguish logically equivalent thoughts. A related problem is that, since composition for Prinz does not yield structurally complex representations, there seems to be nothing to distinguish the type of contents associated with judgements (propositional contents) from those associated lists or even single concepts (for related discussion Fodor 2003). Finally, there are difficulties regarding how to interpret behavioral and neurological evidence that is supposed to support Prinz and Barsalou’s case against amodal representations. For example, Machery (2007) points out that proponents of amodal representations typically suppose that imagery is useful in solving certain types of problems. So to argue against amodal representations, it is not enough to show that sensory representations show up in a task in which experimental subjects are not explicitly told to visualize a solution, since the use of sensory-based imagery in a task is perfectly compatible with there also being amodal representations in play. (For further critical discussion of the form of empiricism that is opposed to amodal representations, see Weiskopf 2007, Dove 2009, and Mahon 2015).

Perhaps the most influential discussion of concepts in relation to the nativism/empiricism debate is Jerry Fodor’s (1975, 1981) argument for the claim that virtually all lexical concepts are innate. Fodor (1975) argued that there are theoretical problems with all models of concept learning in that all such models treat concept learning as hypothesis testing. The problem is that the correct hypothesis invariably employs the very concept to be learned and hence the concept has to be available to a learner prior to the learning taking place. In his (1981), Fodor developed this argument by allowing that complex concepts (and only complex concepts) can be learned in that they can be assembled from their constituents during the learning process. He went on to argue that lexical concepts lack semantic structure and consequently that virtually all lexical concepts must be innate—a position known as radical concept nativism . Fodor’s arguments have had a great deal of influence on debates about nativism and concept learning, especially amongst cognitive scientists. Few if any have endorsed Fodor’s radical conclusions, but many have shaped their views of cognitive development at least in part in response to Fodor’s arguments (Jackendoff 1989, Levin & Pinker 1991, Spelke & Tsivkin 2001, Carey 2009). And Fodor has convinced many that primitive concepts are in principle unlearnable (see, e.g., Pinker 2007). Fodor’s arguments for this conclusion, however, can be challenged in a number of ways. The most direct way to challenge it is to construct an account of what it is to learn a primitive concept and to show that it is immune to Fodor’s challenges (Margolis 1998, Laurence & Margolis 2002, Carey 2009).

Fodor himself changed his view about these issues when he revisited them in Fodor (2008). He now maintains that while considerations about the need for hypothesis testing show that no concepts can be learned, not even complex concepts, this does not require concepts to be innate (Fodor 2008). Instead, Fodor suggests that they are largely acquired via processes that are merely biological in that they don’t admit of a psychological-level description. Though such a “biological” account of concept acquisition does offer an alternative to the innate/learned dichotomy, there are reasons for supposing that many concepts are learned all the same (Margolis & Laurence 2011). These include the fact that a person’s conceptual system is highly sensitive to the surrounding culture. For example, the concept PURGATORY comes from cultural products such as books, stories, and sermons. But clearly these can only succeed in conveying the concept when mediated by the right sort of psychological processes. Acquiring such concepts is a cognitive-level achievement, not a merely biological one.

Although much of the philosophical discussion of concept nativism has focused on Fodor’s radical concept nativism, it is important to note that other less radical approaches to the origins of concepts exist and that these other approaches embrace a fair amount of learning—they just hold that much of this learning is structured by innate special-purpose acquisition systems (for example, Gallistel 1990, Keil 1989, Spelke & Newport 1998, Baillargeon 2008, Carey 2009, Margolis & Laurence 2013, Tooby & Cosmides 2016).

One further issue concerning innate concepts that is in dispute is whether the very idea of innateness makes sense. A common point among those who are skeptical of the notion is the observation that all traits are dependent upon interactions between genes and the environment and that there is no way to fully untangle the two (Elman et al. 1996, Griffiths 2002; see also Clark 1998 and Marcus 2004, and the entry on the distinction between innate and acquired characteristics ). Nonetheless, there are clear differences between models of the mind with empiricist leanings and models of the mind with nativist leanings, and the notion of innateness may be thought to earn its usefulness by marking these differences (Margolis & Laurence (2013). For discussion of different proposals of what innateness is see Ariew (1999), Cowie (1999), Samuels (2002), Mallon & Weinberg (2006), Mameli (2008) and Khalidi (2015).

4. Concepts and natural language

We turn now to the issue of how concepts and thoughts relate to language.

Some philosophers maintain that possession of natural language is necessary for having any concepts (Brandom 1994, Davidson 1975, Dummett 1993) and that the tight connection between the two can be established on a priori grounds. In a well known passage, Donald Davidson summarizes his position as follows:

We have the idea of belief only from the role of belief in the interpretation of language, for as a private attitude it is not intelligible except as an adjustment to the public norm provided by language. It follows that a creature must be a member of a speech community if it is to have the concept of belief. And given the dependence of other attitudes on belief, we can say more generally that only a creature that can interpret speech can have the concept of a thought.
Can a creature have a belief if it does not have the concept of belief? It seems to me it cannot, and for this reason. Someone cannot have a belief unless he understands the possibility of being mistaken, and this requires grasping the contrast between truth and error—true belief and false belief. But this contrast, I have argued, can emerge only in the context of interpretation, which alone forces us to the idea of an objective, public truth. (Davidson 1975, p. 170).

The argument links having beliefs and concepts with having the concept of belief. Since Davidson thinks that non-linguistic creatures can’t have the concept of belief, they can’t have other concepts as well. Why the concept of belief is needed to have other concepts is somewhat obscure in Davidson’s writings (Carruthers 1992). And whether language is necessary for this particular concept is not obvious. In fact, there is an ongoing research program in cognitive science that addresses this very issue. A variety of non-linguistic tasks have been given to animals and infants to determine the extent to which they are able to attribute mental states to others (see Andrews & Beck 2018 for work on animals and Baillargeon et al. 2015 for work on infants). These and related studies provide strong evidence that at least some aspects of theory of mind are nonlinguistic.

Davidson offers a pair of supplementary arguments that may elucidate why he is hesitant to turn the issue over to the cognitive scientists. He gives the example of a man engaging in a non-linguistic task where the man indicates his answer by making a choice, for example, selecting an apple over a pear. Davidson comments that until the man actually says what he has in mind, there will always be a question about the conceptualization guiding his choice. “Repeated tests may make some readings of his actions more plausible than others, but the problem will remain how to determine when he judges two objects of choice to be identical” (1975, p. 163). The second argument points to the difficulties of settling upon a specification of what a non-linguistic creature is thinking. “The dog, we say, knows that its master is home. But does it know that Mr. Smith (who is the master) is home? We have no real idea how to settle, or make sense of, these questions” (1975, p, 163). It’s not clear how seriously Davidson himself takes these arguments. Many philosophers have been unconvinced. Notice that both arguments turn on an underdetermination claim—e.g., that the interpretation of the man’s action is underdetermined by the non-linguistic evidence. But much the same thing is true even if we add what the man says (or to be more precise, if we add what the man utters). The linguistic evidence doesn’t guarantee a correct interpretation any more than the non-linguistic evidence does.

Davidson appears to be employing a very high standard for attributing concepts to animals. In effect, he is asking for proof that our attributions are correct. In contrast, most philosophers who are happy to attribute concepts to animals do so because of a wealth of data that are best explained by appealing to an internal system of representation (e.g., Bermudez 2003, Carruthers 2006, Camp 2009; for overviews within cognitive science, see Gallistel 1990, Bekoff, Allen, & Burghardt 2002, and Shettleworth 2010). For example, many species of birds cache food for later retrieval. Their very survival depends upon their ability to successfully recover, in some cases, more than 10,000 different caches in a single season. Researchers studying one species of caching birds have shown that not only do the birds represent the location of the food, but they integrate this information with information about the quality of the food, its perishability, and whether their caching was observed by other birds. Evidence here comes from demonstrations of selective retrieval and recaching of food items under experimentally controlled conditions. Birds will retrieve more perishable items first. When highly valued food items become highly perishable, they shift strategies to retrieve a higher percentage of less perishable food items. And birds that have themselves stolen food from other birds will selectively recache stored food when they are observed caching it (see Clayton, Bussey, & Dickinson 2003, Emery, Dally, & Clayton 2004). Experimental data of this kind provide evidence for particular concepts in birds (of food types, locations, and so on) as well as surprisingly sophisticated cognitive operations that make use of them.

There is a great deal of controversy among philosophers about the implications of this type of research. Proponents of RTM are, of course, entirely happy with the idea that the scientific theories of what birds are doing can be taken at face value. Other philosophers maintain that if the scientific theories say that birds are computing an algorithm for determining a caching strategy, then this can only be read as a façon de parler. Still others will grant that animals have representations but go on to claim that these representation are of a lesser status, not to be confused with concepts (Brandom 1994, 2000, McDowell 1994).

This raises an interesting question about whether there is a motivated and principled difference between concepts in humans and mere representations in animals (Laurence & Margolis 2012). Philosophers who maintain that there is such a difference often cite the role of concepts in reasoning. For example, Robert Brandom claims that representations in animals do little more than act as reliable mechanisms of discrimination. These representations are supposed to be like thermometers, responding to specific environmental features yet without entering into appropriate inferential processes. However, it’s not clear what counts as an appropriate inferential process, and certainly there is room for differing opinions on this point. Moreover, whatever reasoning amounts to, comparative psychology is replete with examples that suggest that animals are capable of far more than reliable detection. Animals may not be as smart as humans, but that doesn’t mean they are as dumb as thermometers (see Hurley & Nudds 2006 and Carruthers 2006 on reasoning in animals).

Even if it’s agreed that it is possible to have concepts in the absence of language, there is a dispute about how the two are related. Some maintain that concepts are prior to and independent of natural language, and that natural language is just a means for conveying thought (Fodor 1975, Pinker 1994). Others maintain that at least some types of thinking (and hence some concepts) occur in the internal system of representation constituting our natural language competence (Carruthers 1996, 2002, Spelke 2003) or that natural language augments our concepts in significant ways (Lupyan 2012).

The arguments for deciding between these two positions involve a mixture of theoretical and empirical considerations. Proponents of the first view have claimed that language is ambiguous in ways that thought presumably is not. For example, the natural language sentence everyone loves someone could be interpreted to mean that for each person, there is some person that they love, or to mean that everyone loves one and the same person (Pinker 1994). Proponents of the first view have also argued that since language itself has to be learned, thought is prior to language (Fodor 1975; Pinker 1994). A third and similar consideration is that people seem to be able formulate novel concepts which are given a linguistic label later; the concept comes first, the linguistic label second (Pinker 1994).

Proponents of the alternative view—that some thinking occurs in language—have pointed to the phenomenology of thought. It certainly seems as if we are thinking in language when we “hear” ourselves silently talking to ourselves (Carruthers 1996; see also Langland-Hassan & Vicente 2018 on the nature and significance of inner speech). Another type of consideration that proponents of this view highlight is the finding that success on certain tasks (e.g., spatial reorientation that relies on combining landmark information with geometrical information) is selectively impaired when the linguistic system is engaged but not when comparable attention is given to non-linguistic distractors. The suggestion is that solving these tasks requires thinking in one’s natural language and that some of the crucial concepts must be couched linguistically (Hermer-Vazquez, Spelke, & Katsnelson 2001; Shusterman & Spelke 2005; Carruthers 2002; see also Gleitman & Papafragou 2012 for a critical overview of a range of tasks where online processing has been thought to rely on linguistic representation).

Finally, one further issue that bears mentioning is the status of various claims regarding linguistic determinism and linguistic relativity. Linguistic determinism is the doctrine that the language a person speaks both causes her to conceptualize the world in certain ways and limits what she can think about by imposing boundaries on her conceptual system; as a result, people who speak very different languages are likely to conceptualize the world in correspondingly different ways. Linguistic relativity is the weaker doctrine that the language one speaks influences how one thinks.

Linguistic determinism is historically associated with the writings of Benjamin Lee Whorf (Whorf 1956). Whorf was especially interested in the languages of the indigenous people of America. He famously argued that the Hopi both speak and think about time in ways that are incongruent with European languages and thought. Rather than viewing time as a continuum that flows evenly throughout the universe and that can be broken up into countable events occurring in the past, present, and future, the Hopi are supposed to focus on change as a process. Their conceptual system is also supposed to differ from ours in that it embodies a distinction between things that are or have been accessible to perception versus things that are not, where the latter category includes things in the future as well as mythical and mental constructs.

The claim that the Hopi lack our concept of time has not stood up to scrutiny. Whorf used clumsy translations of Hopi speech that concealed the extent to which they talk about time (references to yesterday, tomorrow, days of the week, lunar phases, etc.). More interestingly, Whorf provided no direct evidence of how the Hopi think. Instead, he used the circular reasoning that they don’t think about time as we do because they don’t talk about time as we do. In fact, the Hopi use numerous familiar devices for time keeping, such as calendar strings and sun dials, and their sensitivity to time is evident a wide variety of cultural practices (Pinker 1994).

Linguistic determinism isn’t an especially promising doctrine and has few adherents these days, but linguistic relativity is the subject of a spirited debate (see Gumperz & Levinson 1996, Bowerman & Levinson 2001, and Gentner & Goldin-Meadow 2003). Some recent examples of particular interest include whether language influences how we conceptualize spatial frames of reference (in non-linguistic spatial reasoning) (e.g., Li & Gleitman 2002, Levinson et al. 2002, Levinson 2003, Li et al. 2011), spatial relations (in non-linguistic reasoning) (e.g., Choi & Bowerman 1991, Hespos & Spelke 2004), sex (the impact of grammatical gender) (e.g., Boroditsky, Schmidt, & Phillips 2003) and number (e.g., Gordon 2004, Pica et al. 2004, Laurence & Margolis 2007).

5. Concepts and conceptual analysis

Some of the deepest divides in contemporary philosophy concern the limits of empirical inquiry, the status of conceptual analysis, and the nature of philosophy itself (see, e.g., Chalmers 1996, Jackson 1998, DePaul & Ramsey 1998, Block & Stalnaker 1999, Williamson 2007, Stich 2012, Machery 2017, Strevens 2018). And concepts are right at the center of these disputes. For many, philosophy is essentially the a priori analysis of concepts, which can and should be done without leaving the proverbial armchair. We’ve already seen that in the paradigm case, an analysis embodies a definition; it specifies a set of conditions that are individually necessary and jointly sufficient for the application of the concept. For proponents of traditional conceptual analysis, the analysis of a concept is successful to the extent that the proposed definition matches people’s intuitions about particular cases, including hypothetical cases that figure in crucial thought experiments.

Conceptual analysis has been attractive to philosophers for a number of reasons. One is that it makes sense of a good deal of philosophical practice—what George Bealer (1998) calls the standard justificatory procedure . Thought experiments and the elicitation of intuitions are characteristic features of philosophical practice. If this practice is justified, then there has to be an understanding of what philosophy is that explains why. Conceptual analysis is supposed to provide just what’s needed here. Intuitions can be said to be of value to philosophy precisely because they help us to get clearer about our concepts, especially concepts of intrinsic philosophical interest (JUSTICE, KNOWLEDGE, etc.).

A related attraction is that conceptual analysis explains how philosophy could be an a priori discipline, as many suppose it is. If philosophy is primarily about concepts and concepts can be investigated from the armchair, then the a priori character of philosophy is secured (Jackson 1998).

A third attraction of conceptual analysis is that conceptual analysis has been argued to be a necessary precursor for answering questions about ontological reduction, that is, the sort of reduction that takes place when it’s argued that genes are DNA segments, that sensations are brain states, and so on (Chalmers 1996, Jackson 1998). According to one way of filling this view out, one has to begin with an a priori analysis of the higher-level concept, particularly an analysis that makes explicit its causal relations. One can then appeal to empirical findings regarding the things that actually have those causal relations. For example, neuroscience may reveal that such-and-such brain state has the causal relations that analysis reveals to be constitutive of our concept of pain. In the course of doing this, neuroscience is supposed to be showing us what pain is (Lewis 1966, Armstrong 1968). But neuroscience is only in a position to do this against the background of the philosophical work that goes into articulating the concept. (For detailed treatments of this view of reduction, see Chalmers 1996, 2010 and Jackson 1998—though it should be noted that Chalmers argues that PAIN, and other concepts of conscious mental states, cannot be analyzed solely in terms of their causal relations and concludes from this that consciousness itself is irreducible.) This work has generated a great deal of debate (e.g., Block & Stalnaker 1999, Levine 2001, Laurence & Margolis 2003, Yablo 2008, Papineau 2002).

A fourth attraction is that conceptual analysis may offer normative guidance (Goldman 1986). For instance, epistemologists face the question of whether our inferential practices are justified and, if so, what justifies them. One standard answer is that they can be justified if they conform to our intuitions about what counts as a justified inference (Goldman 1986). In other words, an analysis of our concept of justification is supposed to be all that is needed in order to establish that a set of inference rules is justified. So if it ever turned out that different groups of people employed qualitatively different sets of inferential principles, we could establish the epistemically preferable one by showing that it does a better job of conforming to our concept of justification.

Many philosophers who are opposed to conceptual analysis identify their approach as being naturalistic (e.g., Devitt 1996, Kornblith 2002, Papineau 2013; see also the entry naturalism ). A common theme of this work is that philosophy is supposed to be continuous with science and that philosophical theories are to be defended on largely explanatory grounds, not on the basis of a priori arguments that appeal to intuition. Accordingly, perceived difficulties with conceptual analysis provide arguments for naturalism.

One such argument centers around the failures of the classical theory of concepts. Earlier, in Section 2 , we noted that paradigmatic conceptual analyses require concepts to have classical structure, an assumption that is increasingly difficult to maintain. For this reason, a number of philosophers have expressed skepticism about the viability of conceptual analysis as a philosophical method (e.g., Ramsey 1998, Stich 1992). Others, however, have called into question the connection between conceptual analysis and definitions (Chalmers & Jackson 2001).

Another objection to conceptual analysis is that the intuitions that philosophers routinely rely upon may not be shared. Anyone who teaches philosophy certainly knows that half the time students have the “wrong intuitions”. But who are we to say that they are wrong? And given that people disagree about their intuitions, these can hardly be treated as objective data (Cummins 1998).

Things become even more interesting if we branch out to other cultures. In a preliminary study of East Asian vs. Western intuitions, Jonathan Weinberg, Shaun Nichols, & Stephen Stich (2001) found that East Asians often have the “wrong intuitions” regarding variations on classic philosophical thought experiments, including Gettier-type thought experiments (though see Machery et al 2017 for evidence that some of these intuitions may in fact be universal). At the very least, this work suggests that philosophers should be cautious about moving from their own intuitions to claims about the proper analysis of a concept.

What’s more, the possibility of cultural diversity raises a troubling question for philosophers who want to establish normative claims on the basis of analyses of concepts, such as the concept of justification. Suppose, for example, that East Asian culture offers a different concept of justification than the one that is embedded in Western commonsense thought (assuming for sake of argument that there is a single concept of justification in each culture). In addition, suppose that East Asians employ different inferential practices than our own and that their practices do a fair job of conforming to their concept of justification and that ours do a fair job of conforming to our own. On what basis, then, are we to compare and evaluate these differing practices? Does it really make sense to say that ours are superior on the ground that they conform better to our concept of justification? Wouldn’t this just be a form of epistemic prejudice? After all, the question arises whether, given the two concepts of justification, ours is the one that ought to be used for performing normative epistemic evaluations (Stich 1990; for further discussion see Williamson 2005, Sosa 2009, Stich 2009, Weinberg, Nichols, & Stich 2001, Weinberg et al. 2010).

The critique of traditional philosophical analysis has also generated proposals for various types of normative, revisionary projects. Instead of asking which cases are or are not covered by a concept, they ask how a concept should be modified or what new concept should be adopted in its place, given the practical context in which the concept is used—for example, given the goal of promoting social equality (Haslanger 2012, Cappelen 2018).

Much is at stake in the debate between conceptual analysts and naturalists, and it is likely to be a central topic in the theory of concepts for the foreseeable future.

  • Adams, F. & Campbell, K. (1999). Modality and Abstract Concepts. Behavioral and Brain Sciences , 22: 610.
  • Andrews, K. & Beck, J. (2017). The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Animal Minds , London: Routledge.
  • Ariew, A. (1999). Innateness is Canalization: In Defense of a Developmental Account of Innateness, in V. Hardcastle (ed.), Where Biology Meets Psychology: Philosophical Essays , pp. 117–38. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • Armstrong, D. (1968). A Materialist Theory of Mind , London: Routledge.
  • Atran, S. & Medin, D. (2008). The Native Mind and the Cultural Construction of Nature , Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • Ayer, A.J. (1959). Logical Positivism , New York: The Free Press.
  • Baker, M. (2001). The Atoms of Language: The Mind’s Hidden Rules of Grammar , New York: Basic Books.
  • Baillargeon, R. (2008). Innate Ideas Revisited: For a Principle of Persistence in Infants’ Physical Reasoning. Perspectives on Psychological Science , 3 (1): 2–13.
  • Baillargeon, R., Scott, R.M., He, Z., Sloane, S., Setoh, P., Jin, K.-S., Wu, D., & Bian, L. (2015). Psychological and Sociomoral Reasoning in Infancy, in M.Mikulincer & P.R. Shaver (eds.), APA Handbook of Personality and Social Psychology: Volume 1. Attitudes and Social Cognition , Washington, DC: American Psychological Association, pp. 79–150.
  • Barsalou, L. (1999). Perceptual Symbol Systems. Behavioral and Brain Sciences , 22: 577–609.
  • Barsalou, L., Simmons, W., Barbey, A., & Wilson, C. (2003). Grounding Conceptual Knowledge in Modality-Specific Systems. Trends in Cognitive Science , 7 (2): 84–89.
  • Bealer, G. (1998). Intuition and the Autonomy of Philosophy, in M. DePaul & W. Ramsey (eds.) Rethinking Intuition: The Psychology of Intuition and Its Role in Philosophical Inquiry , Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield, pp. 201–239.
  • Bekoff, M., Allen, C., & Burghardt, G. (2002). The Cognitive Animal: Empirical and Theoretical Perspectives on Animal Cognition , Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • Bennett, M. & Hacker, P. (2008). History of Cognitive Neuroscience , Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.
  • Bermudez, J. (2003). Thinking Without Words , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Block, N. & Stalnaker, R. (1999). Conceptual Analysis and the Explanatory Gap, Philosophical Review , 108 (1): 1–46.
  • Blok, S., Newman, G. & Rips, L.J. (2005). Individuals and Their Concepts, in W.-K. Ahn, R.L. Goldstone, B.C. Love, A.B. Markman, & P. Wolff (eds.), Categorization Inside and Outside the Laboratory: Essays in Honor of Douglas L. Medin , Washington, DC: American Psychological Association, pp. 127–149.
  • Boroditsky, L., Schmidt, L., & Phillips, W. (2003). Sex, Syntax, and Semantics, in D. Gentner & S. Goldin-Meadow (eds.) Language in Mind , Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 61–79.
  • Bowerman, M. & Levinson, S. (2001). Language Acquisition and Conceptual Development , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Brandom, R. (1994). Making It Explicit: Reasoning, Representing, and Discursive Commitment , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • ––– (2000). Articulating Reasons: An Introduction to Inferentialism , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Brewer, W. (1999). Perceptual Symbols: The Power and Limitations of a Theory of Dynamic Imagery and Structured Frames, Behavioral and Brain Sciences , 22: 611–12.
  • Camp, E. (2009). A Language of Baboon Thought?, in R.W. Lurz (ed.) The Philosophy of Animal Minds , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 108–127.
  • Cappelen, H. (2018). Fixing Language: An Essay on Conceptual Engineering , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Carey, S. (1985). Conceptual Change in Childhood , Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • ––– (2009). The Origin of Concepts , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Carruthers, P. (1992). The Animals Issue: Moral Theory in Practice , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • ––– (1996). Language, Thought, and Consciousness , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • ––– (2002). The Cognitive Functions of Language, Behavioral and Brain Sciences , 25: 657–74.
  • ––– (2006). The Architecture of the Mind: Massive Modularity and the Flexibility of Thought , New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Carruthers, P., Laurence, S., & Stich, S. (2005). The Innate Mind: Structure and Contents , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • ––– (2006). The Innate Mind: Culture and Cognition , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • ––– (2007). The Innate Mind: Foundations and the Future , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Chalmers, D. (1996). The Conscious Mind: In Search of a Fundamental Theory , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • ––– (2010). The Character of Consciousness , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Chalmers, D. & Jackson, F. (2001). Conceptual Analysis and Reductive Explanation, Philosophical Review , 110: 315–61.
  • Choi, S. & Bowerman, M. (1991). Learning to Express Motion Events in English and Korean: The Influence of Language-Specific Lexicalization Patterns, Cognition , 41: 83–121.
  • Chomsky, N. (1967). Recent Contributions to the Theory of Innate Ideas, Synthese , 17: 2–11. Reprinted in S. Stich (ed.) Innate Ideas , Berkeley: University of California Press, pp. 121–31.
  • ––– (1975). Reflections on Language , New York: Pantheon.
  • ––– (1980). Rules and Representations , New York: Columbia University Press.
  • ––– (1988). Language and the Problems of Knowledge: The Managua Lectures , Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • Churchland, P. (1981). Eliminative Materialism and Propositional Attitudes, Journal of Philosophy , 78 (2): 67–90.
  • Clark, A. (1993). Associative Engines: Connectionism, Concepts, and Representational Change , Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • ––– (1998). Twisted Tales: Causal Complexity and Cognitive Scientific Explanation, Minds and Machines , 8: 76–99.
  • Clayton, N., Bussey, T., & Dickinson, A. (2003). Can Animals Recall the Past and Plan for the Future? Nature Reviews: Neuroscience , 4: 685–91
  • Cowie, F. (1999). What’s Within: Nativism Reconsidered , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Crain, S. & Pietroski, P. (2001). Nature, Nurture, and Universal Grammar, Linguistics and Philosophy , 24: 139–186.
  • Crane, T. (2015). The Mechanical Mind, Third Edition , London: Routledge.
  • Cummins, R. (1998). Reflection on Reflective Equilibrium, in M. DePaul & W. Ramsey (eds.), Rethinking Intuition: The Psychology of Intuition and Its Role in Philosophical Inquiry , Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield, pp. 113–27.
  • Davidson, D. (1975). Thought and Talk. In his Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Del Pinal, G. (2016). Prototypes as Compositional Components of Concepts, Synthese , 193 (9): 2899–2927.
  • Dennett, D. (1977). A Cure for the Common Code. Reprinted in D. Dennett (1978) Brainstorms , Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • ––– (1978). Brainstorms: Philosophical Essays on Mind and Psychology , Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • ––– (1987). The Intentional Stance , Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • ––– (1991). Consciousness Explained , Boston: Little, Brown and Company.
  • DePaul, M. & Ramsey, W. (1998). Rethinking Intuition: The Psychology of Intuition and Its Role in Philosophical Inquiry , Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.
  • Devitt, M. (1981). Designation , New York: Columbia University Press.
  • ––– (1996). Coming to Our Senses: A Naturalistic Program for Semantic Localism , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Dove, G. (2009). Beyond Perceptual Symbols: A Call for Representational Pluralism, Cognition , 110: 412–431.
  • Dummett, M. (1993). Seas of Language , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Elman, J., Bates, E., Johnson, M., Karmiloff-Smith, A., Parisi, D., and Plunkett, K. (1996). Rethinking Innateness: A Connectionist Perspective on Development , Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • Emery, N., Dally, J., & Clayton, N. (2004). Western Scrub-Jays ( Aphelocoma Californica ) Use Cognitive Strategies to Protect Their Caches from Thieving Conspecifics, Animal Cognition , 7: 37–43.
  • Fodor, J. (1968). The Appeal to Tacit Knowledge, Journal of Philosophy , 65 (20): 627–640.
  • ––– (1975). The Language of Thought , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • ––– (1981). The Present Status of the Innateness Controversy. In his Representations: Philosophical Essays on the Foundations of Cognitive Science , Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • ––– (1987). Psychosemantics: The Problem of Meaning in the Philosophy of Mind , Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • ––– (1998). Concepts: Where Cognitive Science Went Wrong , New York: Oxford University Press.
  • ––– (2003). Hume Variations , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • ––– (2008). LOT 2: The Language of Thought Revisited , New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Fodor, J. & Lepore, E. (1992). Holism: A Shopper’s Guide , Oxford: Blackwell.
  • ––– (1996). The Red Herring and the Pet Fish: Why Concepts Still Can’t Be Prototypes, Cognition , 58: 253–270.
  • Fodor, J. & Pylyshyn, Z. (1988). Connectionism and Cognitive Architecture: A Critical Analysis, Cognition , 28: 3–71.
  • Gallistel, C.R. & King, A. (2009). Memory and the Computational Brain: Why Cognitive Science Will Transform Neuroscience , Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.
  • ––– (1990). The Organization of Learning , Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • Gelman, S. (2003). The Essential Child: Origins of Essentialism in Everyday Thought , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Genone, E. (1963). Theories of Reference and Experimental Philosophy. Philosophy Compass , 7 (2): 152–163.
  • Gentner, D. & Goldin-Meadow, S. (2003). Language in Mind , Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • Gettier, E. (1963). Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Analysis , 23: 121–123.
  • Gleitman, L. & Papafragou, A. (2012). New Perspectives on Language and Thought, in K. Holyoak & R. Morrison (eds.), Oxford Handbook of Thinking and Reasoning , Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 543–568.
  • Goldman, A. (1986). Epistemology and Cognition , Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • Gonnerman, C. & Weinberg, J. (2010). Two Uneliminated Uses for ‘Concepts’: Hybrids and Guides for Inquiry, Behavioral and Brain Sciences , 33: 211–212
  • Goodman, N. (1969). The Emporer’s New Ideas, in S. Hook ( ed. ), Language and Philosophy , New York: NYU Press, pp. 138–42.
  • Gopnik, A., & Meltzoff, A. (1997). Words, Thoughts, and Theories , Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • Gordon, P. (2004). Numerical Cognition Without Words: Evidence from Amazonia, Science , 306: 496–499.
  • Griffiths, P. (2002). What Is Innateness? Monist , 85 (1): 70–85.
  • Gumperz, J. & Levinson, S. (1996). Rethinking Linguistic Relativity , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Hampton, J. (2006). Concepts as Prototypes, in B.H. Ross (ed.), Psychology of Learning and Motivation (Volume 46), New York: Academic Press, pp. 79–113
  • ––– (2010). Concept Talk Cannot Be Avoided, Behavioral and Brain Sciences , 33: 212–213
  • Hampton, J. & Jönsson, M. (2012). Typicality and Compositionality: The Logic of Combining Vague Concepts, in M. Werning, W. Hintzen, & E. Machery (eds.), Oxford Handbook of Compositionality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Haslanger, S. (2012). Resisting Reality: Social Construction and Social Critique , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Hermer-Vazquez, L., Spelke, E., & Katsnelson, A. (2001). Sources of Flexibility in Human Cognition: Dual-Task Studies of Space and Language, Cognitive Psychology , 39: 3–36.
  • Hespos, S. & Spelke, E. (2004). Conceptual Precursors to Language, Nature , 430: 453–456.
  • Hume, D. (1739/1978). A Treatise of Human Nature , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • ––– (1748/1975). Enquiries Concerning Human Understanding and Concerning the Principles of Morals , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Hurley, S. & Nudds, M. (2006) Rational Animals? , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Jackendoff, R. (1989). What is a Concept, that a Person May Grasp It? Mind & Language , 4: 68–102.
  • Jackson, F. (1998). From Metaphysics to Ethics: A Defense of Conceptual Analysis , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Johnson, S.P. (2010). Neuroconstructivism: The New Science of Cognitive Development , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Keil, F. (1989). Concepts, Kinds, and Cognitive Development , Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • Kenny, A. (2010). Concepts, Brains, and Behaviour, Grazer Philosophische Studien , 81 (1): 105–113.
  • Khalidi, M.A. (2015). Innateness as a Natural Cognitive Kind, Philosophical Psychology , 29 (3): 319–333.
  • Kornblith, H. (2002). Knowledge and Its Place in Nature , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Kripke, S. (1972/1980). Naming and Necessity , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Lalumera, E. (2010). Concepts are a Functional Kind, Behavioral and Brain Sciences , 33: 217–218
  • Landau, B. (1982). Will the Real Grandmother Please Stand Up? The Psychological Reality of Dual Meaning Representations, Journal of Psycholinguistic Research , 11 (1): 47–62.
  • Langland-Hassan, P. & Vicente, A. (2018). Inner Speech: New Voices , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Laurence, S. & Margolis, E. (1997). Regress Arguments Against the Language of Thought, Analysis , 57: 60–66.
  • ––– (1999). Concepts and Cognitive Science, in E. Margolis & S. Laurence (eds.), Concepts: Core Readings , Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 3–81.
  • ––– (2001). The Poverty of the Stimulus Argument, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science , 52: 217–76.
  • ––– (2002). Radical Concept Nativism, Cognition , 86: 25–55.
  • ––– (2007). Linguistic Determinism and the Innate Basis of Number, in P. Carruthers, S. Laurence, & S. Stich (eds.), The Innate Mind: Foundations and the Future , New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 139–169.
  • ––– (2012). The Scope of the Conceptual, in E. Margolis, R. Samuels, & S. Stich (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Cognitive Science , New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 291–317.
  • Levin, B. & Pinker, S. (1991). Introduction, in B. Levin & S. Pinker (eds.), Lexical and Conceptual Semantics , Oxford: Blackwell.
  • Levine, J. (2001). Purple Haze: The Puzzle of Consciousness , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • ––– (2010). Demonstrative Thought. Mind & Language , 25 (2): 169–195.
  • Levinson, S. (2003). Space in Language and Cognition: Explorations in Cognitive Diversity , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Levinson, S., Kita, S., Haun, D., & Rasch, B. (2002). Returning the Tables: Language Affects Spatial Reasoning, Cognition , 84: 155–188.
  • Lewis, D. (1966). An Argument for the Identity Theory, Journal of Philosophy , 63 (1): 17–25.
  • Li, P. & Gleitman, L. (2002). Turning the Tables: Language and Spatial Reasoning, Cognition , 83: 265–294.
  • Li, P., Abarbanell, L., Gleitman, L. & Papafragou, A. (2011). Spatial Reasoning in Tenejapan Mayans, Cognition , 120 (1): 33–53.
  • Locke, J. (1690/1975). An Essay Concerning Human Understanding , New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Lupyan, G. (2012). What Do Words Do? Toward a Theory of Language-Augmented Thought, in B.H. Ross (ed.), Psychology of Learning and Motivation (Volume 57), New York: Academic Press, pp. 155–297
  • Machery, E. (2007). Concept Empiricism: A Methodological Critique, Cognition , 104: 19–46.
  • ––– (2009). Doing Without Concepts , New York: Oxford University Press.
  • ––– (2010). Precis of Doing Without Concepts , Behavioral and Brain Sciences , 33: 195–244.
  • ––– (2017). Philosophy within Its Proper Bounds , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Machery, E., Mallon, R., Nichols, S. & Stich, S. (2004). Semantics, Cross-Cultural Style, Cognition , 92: B1–B12.
  • Machery, E., Stich, S., Rose, D., Chatterjee, A., Karasawa, K., Struchiner, N., Sirker, S., Usui, N., & Hashimoto, T. (2017). Gettier Across Cultures. Noûs , 51 (3): 645–664.
  • Mahon, B.Z. (2015). What is Embodied about Cognition? Language, Cognition, and Neuroscience , 30 (4): 420–429.
  • Mallon, R. & Weinberg, J. (2006). Innateness as Closed Process Invariance, Philosophy of Science , 73 (3): 323–344.
  • Mameli, M. (2008). On Innateness: The Clutter Hypothesis and the Cluster Hypothesis. The Journal of Philosophy , 105 (12): 719–736.
  • Manfredi, P. (1993). Tacit Beliefs and Other Doxastic Attitudes. Philosophia , 22 (1): 95–117.
  • Marcus, G. (2001). The Algebraic Mind: Integrating Connectionism and Cognitive Science , Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • ––– (2004). The Birth of the Mind: How a Tiny Number of Genes Creates the Complexities of Human Thought , New York: Basic Books.
  • Margolis, E. (1998). How to Acquire a Concept, Mind & Language , 13: 347–369.
  • Margolis, E. & Laurence, S. (1999). Concepts: Core Readings , Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • ––– (2007). The Ontology of Concepts — Abstract Objects or Mental Representations? Noûs , 41 (4): 561–593.
  • ––– (2010). Concepts and Theoretical Unification, Behavioral and Brain Sciences , 33: 219–220.
  • ––– (2011). Learning Matters: The Role of Learning in Concept Acquisition, Mind & Language , 26 (5): 507–539.
  • ––– (2013). In Defense of Nativism, Philosophical Studies , 165 (2): 693–718.
  • ––– (2015). The Conceptual Mind: New Directions in the Study of Concepts , Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • McClelland, J., Botvinick, M., Noelle, D., Plaut, D., Rogers, T., Seidenberg, M., & Smith, L. (2010). Letting Structure Emerge: Connectionist and Dynamic Systems Approaches to Cognition, Trends in Cognitive Sciences , 14: 348–56.
  • McDowell, J. (1994). Mind and World , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Millikan, R. (2000). On Clear and Confused Ideas , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Murphy, G. (2002). The Big Book of Concepts , Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • Osherson, D., & Smith, E. (1981). On the Adequacy of Prototype Theory as a Theory of Concepts, Cognition , 9: 35–58.
  • Papineau, D. (2002). Thinking About Consciousness , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • ––– (2013). The Poverty of Conceptual Analysis, in M. Haug (ed.), The Armchair or the Laboratory? , New York: Routledge, pp. 166–194
  • Peacocke, C. (1992). A Study of Concepts , Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • ––– (2005). Rationale and Maxims in the Study of Concepts, Noûs , 39 (1): 167–78.
  • Pica, P., Lemer, C., Izard, V., & Dehaene, S. (2004). Exact and Approximate Arithmetic in an Amazonian Indigene Group, Science , 306: 499–503.
  • Pietroski, P. & Crain, S. (2012). The Language Faculty, in E. Margolis, R. Samuels, & S. Stich (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Cognitive Science , New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 361–381.
  • Pinker, S. (1994). The Language Instinct: The New Science of Language and Mind. London: Penguin.
  • ––– (2007). The Stuff of Thought: Language as a Window into Human Nature. London: Penguin.
  • Prinz, J. (2002). Furnishing the Mind: Concepts and Their Perceptual Basis , Cambridge, MA.: MIT Press.
  • Putnam, H. (1967). The ‘Innateness Hypothesis’ and Explanatory Models in Linguistics, Synthese , 17: 12–22; reprinted in H. Putnam, Philosophical Papers (Volume 2: Mind, Language and Reality), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 107–116.
  • ––– (1975). The Meaning of ‘Meaning’, in H. Putnam, Philosophical Papers (Volume 2: Mind, Language and Reality), pp. 215–271, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Quine, W.V.O. (1960). Word and Object , Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • Ramsey, W. (1998). Prototypes and Conceptual Analysis, in M. DePaul & W. Ramsey (eds.), Rethinking Intuition: The Psychology of Intuition and Its Role in Philosophical Inquiry , Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield, pp. 161–77.
  • Robbins, P. (2002). How to Blunt the Sword of Compositionality, Noûs , 36 (2): 313–34.
  • Roberts, I. (2017). The Oxford Handbook of Universal Grammar , Oxford University Press.
  • Rosch, E. (1978). Principles of Categorization, in E. Rosch & B. Lloyd (eds.), Cognition and Categorization , Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, pp. 27–48.
  • Rosch, E., & Mervis, C. (1975). Family Resemblances: Studies in the Internal Structure of Categories, Cognitive Psychology , 7: 573–605.
  • Sampson, G. (2005). The “Language Instinct” Debate , revised edition, London: Continuum.
  • Samuels, R. (2002). Nativism in Cognitive Science, Mind & Language , 17 (3): 233–65.
  • Samuels, R. & Ferreira, M. (2010). Why Don’t Concepts Constitute a Natural Kind, Behavioral and Brain Sciences , 33: 222–223.
  • Shapiro, L. (2004). The Mind Incarnate , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Shettleworth, S. (2010). Cognition, Evolution, and Behavior, 2nd edition , New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Shusterman, A. & Spelke, E. (2005). Language and the Development of Spatial Reasoning, in P. Carruthers, S. Laurence, & S. Stich (eds.), The Innate Mind: Structure and Contents , New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 89–106.
  • Smith, E., & Medin, D. (1981). Categories and Concepts , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Sosa, E. (2009). A Defense of the Use of Intuitions in Philosophy, in D. Murphy & M. Bishop (eds.), Stich and His Critics , Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.
  • Spelke, E.S. (2003). What Makes Us Smart? Core Knowledge and Natural Language, in D. Gentner & S. Goldin-Meadow (eds.), Language in Mind , Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp 277–311.
  • Spelke, E.S. & Kinzler, K.D. (1992). Core Knowledge, Developmental Science , 10 (1): 89–96.
  • Spelke, E.S. & Newport, E. (1998). Nativism, Empiricism, and the Development of Knowledge, in W. Damon (series ed.) and R.M. Lerner (volume ed.), Handbook of Child Psychology ( Volume 1: Theoretical Models of Human Development ), fifth edition, New York: Wiley, pp. 275–340.
  • Spelke, E.S. & Tsivkin, S. (2001). Initial Knowledge and Conceptual Change: Space and Number, in M. Bowerman & S. Levinson (eds.), Language Acquisition and Conceptual Development , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Stich, S. (1990). The Fragmentation of Reason , Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • ––– (1992). What Is a Theory of Mental Representation? Mind , 101 (402): 243–61.
  • ––– (2009). Reply to Sosa. In D. Murphy & M. Bishop (eds.). Stich and His Critics , Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.
  • ––– (2012). Collected Papers (Volume 2: Knowledge, Rationality, and Morality, 1978–2010), Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Strevens, M. (2018). Thinking Off Your Feet: How Empirical Psychology Vindicates Armchair Psychology , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Strohminger, N. & Moore, B. (2010). Banishing the Thought, Behavioral and Brain Sciences , 33: 225–226
  • Tooby, J. & Cosmides, L. (2016). The Theoretical Foundations of Evolutionary Psychology. In D. Buss (ed.) The Handbook of Evolutionary Psychology, Second Edition , Wiley, pp. 3–87.
  • Van Gelder, T. (1995). What Might Cognition Be, If Not Computation? Journal of Philosophy , 91: 345–381.
  • Vicente, A. & Manrique, F.M. (2016). The Big Concepts Paper: A Defense of Hybridism, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science , 67: 59–88.
  • Weinberg, J., Gonnerman, C., Buckner, C., & Alexander, J. (2010). Are Philosophers Expert Intuiters? Philosophical Psychology , 23 (3): 331–355.
  • Weinberg, J., Nichols, S., & Stich, S. (2001). Normativity and Epistemic Intuitions, Philosophical Topics , 29 (1&2): 429–460.
  • Weiskopf, D. (2007). Concept Empiricism and the Vehicles of Thought, Journal of Consciousness Studies , 14: pp. 156–183.
  • ––– (2009). The Plurality of Concepts, Synthese , 169: 145–173.
  • ––– (2010). The Theoretical Indispensability of Concepts, Behavioral and Brain Sciences , 33: 228–229
  • Whorf, B. (1956). Language, Thought, and Reality , Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • Williamson, T. (2005). Armchair Philosophy, Metaphysical Modality and Counterfactual Thinking, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society , 105: 1–23.
  • ––– (2007). The Philosophy of Philosophy , Oxford: Blackwell.
  • Wittgenstein, L. (1953/1958). Philosophical Investigations , 3rd edition, G.E.M. Anscombe (trans.), Oxford: Blackwell.
  • Wright, C. (1989). The Verification Principle: Another Puncture—Another Patch, Mind , 98: 611–622.
  • Yablo, S. (2008). Thoughts: Papers on Mind, Meaning, and Modality , Oxford University Press.
  • Zalta, E. (2001). Fregean Senses, Modes of Presentation, and Concepts, Philosophical Perspectives , 15: 335–359.
How to cite this entry . Preview the PDF version of this entry at the Friends of the SEP Society . Look up topics and thinkers related to this entry at the Internet Philosophy Ontology Project (InPhO). Enhanced bibliography for this entry at PhilPapers , with links to its database.
  • Concepts , entry in the category philosophy of mind at PhilPapers.org.

abilities | animal: cognition | belief | cognition: embodied | connectionism | Frege, Gottlob | innate/acquired distinction | innateness: and language | knowledge: analysis of | language of thought hypothesis | linguistics: philosophy of | materialism: eliminative | mental content: nonconceptual | mental representation | mind: computational theory of | naturalism | Vienna Circle

Copyright © 2019 by Eric Margolis < eric . margolis @ ubc . ca > Stephen Laurence < s . laurence @ sheffield . ac . uk >

  • Accessibility

Support SEP

Mirror sites.

View this site from another server:

  • Info about mirror sites

The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy is copyright © 2023 by The Metaphysics Research Lab , Department of Philosophy, Stanford University

Library of Congress Catalog Data: ISSN 1095-5054

Rare archaeological find uncovers evidence of 12,000-year-old Indigenous rituals

Email

In 2019 and 2020, remarkable Indigenous archaeology took place in the east of Victoria, in a cave in the foothills of the Australian Alps. The Snowy River flows nearby. The area, at Cloggs Cave near Buchan, is GunaiKurnai Country.

The researchers - from the GunaiKurnai Land and Waters Aboriginal Corporation , representing Traditional Owners, and Monash University - found two sticks each protruding from its own tiny fireplace deeply buried in a section of the cave.

They are no ordinary installations, each having significant cultural value. The team's new paper, in the scientific journal Nature Human Behaviour , explains profound insights into the rich heritage of local Indigenous peoples 11,000 to 12,000 years ago in this isolated pocket of Australia's southeast.

The paper also highlights how earlier research - which reduced local cave use to group shelter and the consumption of food - missed key cultural dimensions of how and why some people used caves, such as Cloggs Cave.

The researchers say this kind of work was done differently then, without consultation or permission from local Aboriginal Traditional Owners.

Aboriginal families were assumed to have lived in the caves. But researchers say this was a product of ‘subsistence thinking’ prevalent in Australian archaeology at the time. Now it is known that culture is much richer, and combining local community knowledge and research priorities with the latest scientific methods in community-driven research has now shed new details of the deep connections that GunaiKurnai have with their Ancestral caves.

The new research was requested and co-led by the GunaiKurnai, with the ethical protocols for the research written into a memorandum of understanding, checked for ethical compliance and signed in 2018.

GunaiKurnai Elder Uncle Russell Mullett said the important factor was to

“... establish the relationship, the trust, and the ability to bring a lot of people in to help to reinterpret this cave, and the journey.”

He says the 1970s approach to research, and the report that resulted from it, contained “misinformation or misinterpretation” of the findings. “Some things might be right,” he says, “but a lot of it wasn't”.

He says the new dig is “remarkable” and was done in a partnership between the GunaiKurnai Land and Waters Aboriginal Corporation and transdisciplinary academic researchers coordinated through the Monash Indigenous Studies Centre.

It revealed “cultural knowledge passed down through 500 generations”.

“… for these artefacts to survive is just amazing," he says. "They’re telling us a story. They’ve been waiting here all this time for us to learn from them. A reminder that we are a living culture still connected to our ancient past. It’s a unique opportunity to be able to read the memoirs of our Ancestors and share that with our community.”

The paper explains that in societies without writing, archaeological evidence for ethnographically known rituals have only rarely been documented over more than a few hundred years.

Since early colonial times in the 1840s – covering the period of GunaiKurnai ethnographic writings - GunaiKurnai caves were not used as everyday living places but as “secluded retreats for the performance of rituals by Aboriginal medicine men and women known as ‘mulla-mullung'."

Researchers found buried 11,000- and 12,000-year-old miniature fireplaces with protruding trimmed wooden artefacts or sticks made of Casuarina wood, smeared with animal or human fat. They had been burned at very low temperatures, each for a short time. No food remains were associated with the fireplaces, "matching the configuration and contents of GunaiKurnai ritual installations described in nineteenth-century ethnography".

Those wonderfully preserved buried miniature fireplaces with their prepared protruding sticks revealed by the archaeology date back to the end of the last Ice Age.

They are Australia's oldest known wooden artefacts. They also signal some 500 generations of cultural transmission of a very particular ritual performance.

The researchers say no other ritual in the world has the tell-tale archaeological remains traceable so far back in time as these sticks.

The researchers write that the way the single sticks were prepared means the fireplaces were not for cooking or heating, and they cite nineteenth century ethnography, in particular Alfred Howitt , an English geologist and pioneer ethnographer who migrated to Victoria in 1852. He recorded vast amounts of information about GunaiKurnai culture from GunaiKurnai Elders and other community members through the latter half of the nineteenth century, including details of cave use and rituals.

Howitt described ritual fires and smearing fat or fluids on 'magic' throwing sticks imbued with great spiritual power. These wooden implements were called ‘murrawan’, and their makers and users ‘bungil murrawun'. Each of the GunaiKurnai clan groups had their own cave, and each cave had a “doctor, called a Mulla-mullung” says Uncle Russell Mullett, who could cure but also summon harm, so they were both feared and sought after.

“It's very, very exciting,” he says of the new findings. “Extraordinary. It's a time capsule that's preserved things so well. Everything that's come out of the small excavations has produced information that's opened the door to a broader understanding of the cultural use of the place.”

Read more  Magic, culture, and stalactites: How Aboriginal perspectives are transforming archaeological histories

Professor Bruno David, an anthropological archaeologist from the Monash Indigenous Studies Centre , says the project unearthed “astonishing” finds.

“You don't find these kinds of things in archaeology because the wood has normally disintegrated. Not only that, these are really special fireplaces.

“People did not use them to make heat or to cook things. We know that because of the scientific findings that were made during the excavations, together with the cultural knowledge that the Elders have and that Howitt wrote about from GunaiKurnai knowledge-keepers of the time."

The sticks and fireplaces are “hidden stories” that remained buried under the soil for thousands of years - “that's culturally meaningful not just for science, but more importantly for the community.

“This kind of research, it's cultural research, so it's got to be based on trust, on understanding and respect and mutual learning as well,” Uncle Russell Mullett explains. “The 1970s excavations gave nothing back to the community, whereas now, 50-odd years later, there is a kind of redress.

“The cultural lens of it is the important part. Yes, we can talk about science and write science papers, but it's the actual culture, what was happening here and what was going on, that’s the big story.”

  • Cloggs cave
  • Indigenous culture
  • Archaeology
  • Indigenous history
  • Indigenous rituals

image

Russell Mullett

Traditional Custodian — Kurnai, Indigenous Knowledge

image

Bruno David

Professor, Monash Indigenous Studies Centre, Monash University

mental representation

Listening to Indigenous peoples’ knowledge

It’s time to ditch colonial thinking and listen to the wisdom of Indigenous peoples to advance health and wellbeing, and to forge a sustainable planetary future.

mental representation

Closing the Gap’s failure to address Indigenous mental health

As Closing the Gap policy failures are laid bare in the Productivity Commission’s latest report, a new study aims to quantify the gap in Indigenous mental health and economic insecurity.

mental representation

Applying an ‘Indigenous paradigm’ to tackle rheumatic heart disease

What began as a heart research project looking at ways to understand a potentially fatal but preventable disease has evolved from the biomedical into one more in keeping with an Indigenous perspective.

mental representation

The business of blending Indigenous knowledge

We can tap into both First Nations and Western leadership concepts to create the next generation of Indigenous business leaders.

mental representation

A voice from the past: William Cooper's dream of Aboriginal representation in Parliament

Ninety years ago, the Yorta Yorta leader was asking for a means by which Australia’s lawmakers could be informed of the views of Aboriginal people.

You may republish this article online or in print under our Creative Commons licence. You may not edit or shorten the text, you must attribute the article to Monash Lens, and you must include the author’s name in your republication.

If you have any questions, please email [email protected]

Republishing Guidelines

https://lens.monash.edu/republishing-guidelines

image

Call or Text the Maternal Mental Health Hotline

Parents: don’t struggle alone

The National Maternal Mental Health Hotline provides free, confidential mental health support. Pregnant people, moms, and new parents can call or text any time, every day.

Start a call: 1-833-TLC-MAMA (1-833-852-6262)

Text now: 1-833-TLC-MAMA (1-833-852-6262)

Use TTY: Use your preferred relay service or dial 711 , then 1-833-852-6262 .

Learn more about the Hotline

  • Programs & Impact
  • Focus Areas
  • Maternal and Child Health Workforce Development
  • Workforce Development Projects

Kentucky Mental Health Care Access for Pediatric Populations

Project profile.

Andrew Waters Phone: 502-564-3193 Email: [email protected]

Goals and objectives:

Methodology:, coordination:, evaluation:.

Dissemination of survey tools, and data evaluation/analyzation will occur in collaboration with all supporting agencies. Evaluation will be completed internal with review of multiple data sets and by independent evaluators. The independent evaluators will coordinate the data collection tools, data entry requirements and definitions, data evaluation/analysis, and program reporting.

IMAGES

  1. PPT

    mental representation

  2. PPT

    mental representation

  3. Visual Mental Representations in Adults with Autism

    mental representation

  4. PPT

    mental representation

  5. PPT

    mental representation

  6. Meaning and Mental Representation by Robert Cummins

    mental representation

VIDEO

  1. From your mental representation to the reality you display

  2. Cognitive Psychology (Class #12)

  3. Importance of Mental Health Representation

  4. Why You Defend Your Abuser (Psychoanalytic Perspective)

  5. Culture, Mind & Brain 2.1: Representations: Intro by Samuel Veissière

  6. Lec 9

COMMENTS

  1. Mental Representation

    Mental Representation. The notion of a "mental representation" is, arguably, in the first instance a theoretical construct of cognitive science. As such, it is a basic concept of the Computational Theory of Mind, according to which cognitive states and processes are constituted by the occurrence, transformation and storage (in the mind ...

  2. Mental representation

    A mental representation (or cognitive representation), in philosophy of mind, cognitive psychology, neuroscience, and cognitive science, is a hypothetical internal cognitive symbol that represents external reality or its abstractions.. Mental representation is the mental imagery of things that are not actually present to the senses. In contemporary philosophy, specifically in fields of ...

  3. What are Mental Representations?

    Abstract. Mental representation is one of the core theoretical constructs within cognitive science and, together with the introduction of the computer as a model for the mind, is responsible for enabling the "cognitive turn" in psychology and associated fields. Conceiving of cognitive processes, such as perception, motor control, and ...

  4. Introduction

    This book explores the philosophical and scientific debates about mental representations, their semantic properties, and their explanatory role in different paradigms of cognitive science. It covers topics such as classicism, connectionism, dynamical theories, predictive processing, naturalizing intentionality, and more.

  5. (PDF) What is mental representation? And how does it relate to

    The relationship hetween mental representation and consciousness is considered. What it means to 'represent', and several types of representation (e.g., analogue, digital, spatial, linguistic ...

  6. Representational Theories of Consciousness

    The leading representational approaches to (1) and (2) are "higher-order representation" theories, which divide into "inner sense" or "higher-order perception" views, "acquaintance" accounts, and "higher-order thought" theories. For discussion of those, see the entry on higher-order theories of consciousness. 1.

  7. Mental Representations

    A mental representation is a theoretical construct to explain ongoing information processing in the human brain. It consists of a vehicle, a representandum, and a triadic relation between them, which can be sensory, non-conceptual, or conceptual.

  8. Mental Imagery

    Throughout the history of philosophy imagistic mental representations have been routinely contrasted with abstract, linguistic representations (see Yolton 1996 for a summary). So the assumption here is that there is a sharp contrast between two different kinds of mental representations: imagistic ones, like mental imagery and abstract ...

  9. Representationalism and rationality: why mental representation is real

    Our argument shows that mental representations are necessary for instrumental rationality and must have causally relevant mechanisms, contents, and vehicles. While there are potential rebuttals to this claim, our opponents must explain how agents can be rational without having mental representations. Therefore, we aim to dispense with the anti ...

  10. Representation (Mental)

    The term "mental representation" is sometimes used to cover any mental item which is semantically evaluable, i.e. which has content, truth-value, refers to something, possesses truth-conditions, or is about something.Under this broad construal its extension includes beliefs, thoughts, memories, desires, perceptions and all other mental phenomena exhibiting the feature of intentionality.

  11. Mental Representations

    Mental representations are, in short, objects and structures in the mind with semantic properties. More precisely, mental representations are information-containing, physically-realized structures in the mind that allow us to perceive, make sense of, process, understand, and recall all stimuli. In the area of media processing and media effects ...

  12. What are Mental Representations?

    The topic of this book is mental representation, a theoretical concept that lies at the core of cognitive science. Together with the idea that thinking is analogous to computational processing, this concept is responsible for the "cognitive turn" in the sciences of the mind and brain since the 1950s. Conceiving of cognitive processes (such as perception, reasoning, and motor control) as ...

  13. Insights into embodied cognition and mental imagery from ...

    Mental representations allow humans to think about, remember and communicate about an infinite number of concepts. A key question within cognitive psychology is how the mind stores and accesses ...

  14. What are Mental Representations?

    A chapter that develops a novel version of the representational theory of mind (RTM), which holds that the mind is stocked with mental representations: mental items that represent. It argues that mental representations are abstract types that mark the exercise of representational capacities, and applies C-RTM to debates over the nature and role of mental representations.

  15. (PDF) Mental Representations, Psychology of

    A representation, mental or otherwise, is a system of. symbols. The system of symbols is isomorphic to. another system (the represented system) so that. conclusions drawn through the processing of ...

  16. What is Mental Representation? And How Does It Relate to Consciousness?

    The relationship between mental representation and consciousness is considered. What it means to 'represent', and several types of representation (e.g., analogue, digital, spatial, linguistic, mathematical), are described. Concepts relevant to mental representation in general (e.g., multiple levels of processing, structure/process differences, mapping) and in specific domains (e.g., mental ...

  17. Mental representations

    This video is part of an online course, Intro to Psychology. Check out the course here: https://www.udacity.com/course/ps001.

  18. Mental Representations and Their Analysis: An Epistemological

    This chapter explores the nature and assessment of mental models, internal cognitive structures that play a key role in problem solving and learning. It adopts a naturalistic epistemology and focuses on complex and ill-structured problems that involve multiple acceptable solutions.

  19. The heterogeneity of mental representation: Ending the imagery ...

    Depictive mental representations might functionally bridge propositional information to depictive perception, allowing stored depictive information to change how we experience the world. Next Chapter. Given the preponderance of recent data, from many different sources, one can reasonably conclude that humans can use at least two forms of mental ...

  20. Why Representation Matters and Why It's Still Not Enough

    In 2019, the Pew Research Center reported that the general US population significantly changed their views of same-sex marriage in just 15 years—with 60% of the population being opposed in 2004 ...

  21. Mental Representation in Medieval Philosophy

    The notions of mental representation and intentionality are intrinsically related in contemporary philosophy of mind, since it is usually thought that a mental state has content or is about something other than itself due to its representational nature. These notions have a parallel history in medieval philosophy as well and are now well ...

  22. 'Who's a clever boy!' Why your dog is even smarter than you think

    "The nature of the 'mental representation' has a history of long-debate in psychology, and some researchers argue that we can think of mental representations as 'mental images'," Dr ...

  23. New paper on Young People's Involvement and Under-Representation ...

    This paper provides a practical resource for researchers considering involving young people in the research process, and suggests what data should be collected to improve reporting on the diversity of the young people involved. The mental health of young people (aged 16-25 years) is a growing ...

  24. Mental Representations: A dual coding approach

    It discusses the philosophy of science associated with the dual coding approach, emphasizing the advantages of empiricism in the study of cognitive phenomena and shows that the fundamentals of the theory have stood up well to empirical challenges over the years. Keywords: cognitive representations, internal representations, cognitive problems ...

  25. Novel online enfacement illusion for investigating self-perception in

    Background Remote research methods and interventions for mental health disorders have become increasingly important, particularly for conditions like eating disorders (EDs). Embodiment illusions, which induce feelings of ownership over another person?s body or body parts, offer valuable insights into the mechanisms underlying self-perception issues in EDs and potential interventions. However ...

  26. Concepts

    The mental representation view of concepts is the default position in cognitive science (Carey 2009, Pinker 2007) and enjoys widespread support in the philosophy of mind, particularly among philosophers who view their work as being aligned with research in cognitive science (e.g., ...

  27. Rare archaeological find uncovers evidence of 12,000-year-old

    Closing the Gap's failure to address Indigenous mental health . ... William Cooper's dream of Aboriginal representation in Parliament . Ninety years ago, the Yorta Yorta leader was asking for a means by which Australia's lawmakers could be informed of the views of Aboriginal people.

  28. Kentucky Mental Health Care Access for Pediatric Populations

    Goals include increasing pediatric mental health surveillance capacity and quality, use of pediatric mental health data to inform prevention and treatment interventions, enhancement of telehealth capacity, and dissemination of prevention materials. ... An Advisory Board with multidisciplinary and multiagency representation will be convened. The ...